Divine Exposures: Religion and Imposture in Colonial India
By Dr. Joshua Barton Scott
Department of Religion Duke University
Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Religion in the Graduate School of Duke University
ABSTRACT
My dissertation asks how narratives of religious fraud have been used to rethink Hinduism. It begins in a theoretical register by arguing that the unmasking of charlatans serves as a metonym for the secularizing procedures of modernity more broadly. Tales of charlatans exposure by secularist skeptics promise a disenchanted world freed from the ill-gotten influence of sham divines; such tales evacuate the immanent frame of charismatic god-men, thereby allowing the extension and consolidation of secular power. I trace the trope of charlatanic exposure, beginning with Enlightenment anxieties about priestcraft, continuing on to nineteenth century criticisms of religion, and then making a lateral move to colonial India. I suggest that by the 1830s it had become difficult for many English critics to extricate the problem of priestly imposture from the broader problematic of empire and, more specifically, from the specter of the crafty brahmin. I track the cultural crosscurrents that conjoined English and Indian anticlericalisms, not only to insist on the centrality of colonial thinkers to the constitution of modernity, but also to reconsider modernity s putative secularity. The anticlerical modernity that I identify brings religious and secular skeptics together in a shared war on sacerdotal charisma, best observed at the interstices of empire.
The dissertation disperses the intellectual lineage of the imposture theory of religion by rerouting it through colonial India. The imposture theory, or the notion that religion is but a ruse concocted by crafty priests to dupe gullible masses, was central to the emergence of secular modernity and its mistrust of religion. Closely associated with the
English and French Enlightenments, it was also pervasive in British polemics against Indian religions. My dissertation demonstrates how in its colonial redeployment the imposture theory came to abut Indic imaginaries of religious illusion, ranging from folkloric spoofs of gurus authority to philosophical debates about the ontological status of maya. Starting from the religious controversies of the colonial era, my interrogation of Indic illusion extends from the ninth century philosopher Shankaracharya to the sixteenth century saint Vallabhacharya to the twentieth century guru Osho. Its focus, however, is on three nineteenth century religious reformers: Karsandas Mulji, Dayanand Saraswati, and H.P Blavatsky. Through archival research, textual analysis (in Hindi, Gujarati, and English), and theoretical inquiry, I insinuate these three colonial thinkers into the history of the imposture theory of religion. In doing so, my aim is to contribute to scholarship on the genealogy of religion, particularly in colonial contexts.
CONTENTS
Abstract ........................................................................... iv
Acknowledgements .. vii
Introduction 1
1: The History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations . 40
2: Priestly Despots .. 71
3: Guru is God . 112
4: Pur!"ic Popery 171
5: A Skeptic s Medium . 217
Conclusion 266
Bibliography 281
Biography . 303
First, I would like to thank my dissertation committee. Bruce Lawrence, ever encouraging, was a great support throughout the research and the writing of this dissertation; I was lucky to have him as chair. Leela Prasad, Richard Jaffe, David Gilmartin, and Srinivas Aravamudan all provided incisive feedback on the dissertation itself, as well as invaluable support throughout my career as a graduate student. I also benefited immensely from the support and advice of other Triangle-area faculty. In particular, I would like to thank Tom Tweed, Randall Styers, Sandy Freitag, and Satti Khanna.
My dissertation research was made possible by fellowships from the American
Institute of Indian Studies, the American Institute of Pakistan Studies, and Duke University.
I thank all of those institutions for their generous financial support. Jawaharlal Nehru
University provided me with an institutional base in India, and I would like to thank Susan Viswanathan in particular for all of her help during the nine months in which I was affiliated with JNU. Additionally, I would like to thank the staff of the following libraries and archives: the British Library s Asian and African Studies Reading Room, Cambridge
University Library, the Victoria and Albert Museum, the National Archives of India, the Nehru Memorial Museum and Library, the Maharashtra State Archives, the Cama Institute, the Forbes Gujarati Sabh!, the Asiatic Society of Mumbai, and the Theosophical Society s Adyar Library and Research Centre. The staff of the Forbes Gujarati Sabh! deserves particular thanks for their truly remarkable assistance.
Portions of Chapter 5 have previously appeared in article form as Miracle Publics:
Theosophy, Christianity, and the Coulomb Affair, History of Religions 49:2 (November 2009): 172-196 ( 2009 by the University of Chicago Press). I thank the University of Chicago Press for permission to reproduce that material here.
While abroad, I benefited from the advice of several senior scholars. Particular thanks are due to Usha Thakkar, Amrita Shodhan, and Geraldine Forbes. At an earlier phase of the project, Ashis Nandy and Makarand Paranjape offered both encouragement and logistical support, and I thank them both. My year in the archives would have been far drabber without the company of friends. For the pints in London and Cambridge, and also for the housing, I would like to thank Robert Ricks, Hilary Smith, Cornelius O Boyle, Alice Fodor, Michael Thompson, Will Erikson, and Caitlin Anderson. The Delhi winter was made warmer by Dann Naseemullah, Surita Parashar, Julie Hughes, Brandon Marsh, and Paul Staniland, as well Prabha and the staff of Manushi. Special thanks go to Leo Mirani for showing me such a very good time in Bombay. Thanks also to Anuja Ghosalkar, Rasheed Wadia, Raghu Karnad, Girish Karnad, and Munni Kabir for their hospitality in that city. Back in the States, many friends provided me with invaluable research advice: particular thanks are due to Matt Cook and Pinki Vaishnava. For sharing work or providing useful leads, thanks go, in addition to those above, to James Tabor, Mitra Sharafi, and Chris Pinney. Additionally, I would like to thank Leela Gandhi, who proved both an inspiration and a calming influence during the anxious final months of my Ph.D.
Completing a Ph.D., seldom a straightforward task, requires forms of support far more intangible than those enumerated above. Without the steadfastness of friends, I would not have gotten this far. Here, I will simply pause to thank my graduate school colleagues for seeing me through: Susanna Drake, Lori Baron, Kyle Smith, Kristi UpsonSaia, Kate Blanchard, Ali Aslam, Jacob Remes, Mari Armstrong-Hough, Mitch Fraas, Brett and Cristina Wilson, Youshaa Patel, SherAli Tareen, Isaac Weiner, and Jenna Tiitsman. Without my family, I cannot imagine ever having embarked on the academic life to begin with: thanks to Catherine and John Bishir for giving me a home in Raleigh, and to Jean, Thornton, and Lucile Scott for homes in all the other places for, that is, a lifetime of love and support. Finally, thanks to Daniel Elam for following me, and this project, over some very long distances. Whether in Chapel Hill or Durham, London or Delhi, Bombay or
Chicago, he s been an incomparable companion.
The abolition of religion as the illusory happiness of men is a demand for their real happiness. The call to abandon their illusions about their condition is a call to abandon a condition which requires illusions. Karl Marx, 1843 [1]
The divine pretender stood exposed, and he knew it. His head and hands ceased their ecstatic gyrations, and he confessed to the crowd that the Goddess had left him. The Rev. William Bowley was pleased. A man on a mission, he had rushed to the banyan tree earlier that 1820 morning, upon learning of the blacksmith who claimed to speak with a voice divine. Bowley came to the banyan with a message: I told them that several of them seemed to have combined together; and to have contrived this scheme to deceive the people in order to extort money from them. Hearing his words, the crowd began to laugh. As Bowley later wrote in his journal, they acknowledged that it was no more than I had said. [2]
Bowley s tale, though presented as fact, is necessarily part fable. There below the banyan, the British missionary enacted a simple morality play that has proved one of modernity s most potent mythologies. Three stock characters take the stage: the imposter, the skeptic, and the duped. In this tale, the first and the second characters vie for control of the third. Despite their enmity, these two non-duped figures are more like each other than either is like the crowd; sunk in credulity, its too-easy belief sets it at an irreducible remove from those who see through illusion. Indeed, the entire tale is predicated on the stark separation of belief from doubt. This definitive rupture distinguishes the players, and it secures the tale s purportedly happy ending. In the fable of divine exposure, nary a trace of faith can haunt a crowd once delivered to the certitudes of disbelief.
In India, British colonialism used the imposture narrative to provide a moral justification for empire. British skeptics would liberate Indians, and especially Hindus, from the despotic enchantments of their fake divines from what one observer called the tyrannical swami-ism of modern India. [3] Imperial ideologues adapted a long history of English anticlericalism to a colonial context where screeds against sacerdotal authority served a distinctive function. As Indian culture became firmly identified with religion, allegations of religious fraud were able to breach this last domain of native sovereignty. Precisely because it was overdetermined by imperial discourse, however, belief emerged in colonial India as a highly resonant mode of cultural and political praxis. In doubt s empire, acts of belief were often the only acts that could challenge secular authority.
This dissertation interrogates the discourse of religious fraud in the nineteenth century. It begins by arguing that the unmasking of charlatans serves as a metonym for the secularizing procedures of colonial modernity. Tales of charlatans exposure by secularist skeptics promise a disenchanted world freed from the ill-gotten influence of sham divines; they evacuate the immanent frame of charismatic god-men and thereby
allow the extension and consolidation of secular power. I trace the trope of charlatanic exposure, beginning with Enlightenment anxieties about priestcraft, continuing on to nineteenth century criticisms of religion, and then making a lateral move to colonial India. I suggest that by the 1830s it had become difficult for many British critics to extricate the problem of priestly imposture from the broader problematic of empire and, more specifically, from the specter of the crafty brahmin. [4] I track the cultural crosscurrents that conjoined British and Indian anticlericalisms, not only to insist on the centrality of colonial thinkers to the constitution of modernity, but also to reconsider modernity s putative secularity. The anticlerical modernity that I identify brings religious and secular skeptics together in a shared war on sacerdotal charisma, best observed at the interstices of empire.
The dissertation thus takes up the imposture theory of religion the idea that religion per se is a fraud perpetrated on humanity, a nefarious ruse concocted by clever priests to dupe and control the gullible masses and reroutes it through colonial India. Because of its polemic mobility, priestcraft could be appropriated by the colonized and refitted to cultural contexts well beyond the fold of Western Christendom. I show how in its colonial redeployment the imposture theory came to abut Indic imaginaries of religious illusion, ranging from folkloric spoofs of gurus authority to philosophical debates about the ontological status of m!y!. I use colonial-era controversies to a sketch history of illusion that extends from the ninth-century philosopher "a#kar!c!rya to the sixteenth-century saint Vallabhac!rya to the twentieth-century
guru Osho. My focus, however, is on three nineteenth-century religious reformers:
Karsand!s Mulj$, Day!nand Saraswat$, and H.P Blavatsky. Through archival research, textual analysis (in Hindi, Gujarati, and English), and theoretical inquiry, I insinuate these three colonial thinkers into the history of the imposture theory of religion.
In a sense, the dissertation revisits and rewrites William Howitt s The Popular
History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (1833), a text discussed at length in Chapter 1. Riding the newly globalized concept religion, Howitt mounted an ostensibly universal critique of priestcraft, sweeping up Greeks and Incas, Druids and Hindus into a one grand anticlerical narrative. By contrast, I will call attention to the history of which Howitt himself was a part: how the discursive object priestcraft was recalibrated and remobilized during the era of empire. Where Howitt wrote a vertical history of priestly imposture from its postdiluvian origins, I emphasize the horizontal trajectories of priestcraft as it crept rhizomatically across the discursive networks of empire. Priestcraft brought India s gurus, swamis, and pandits, its mullahs and pirs, into intimate congress with the clerics of the Christian West, its priests, popes, and bishops, its vicars and pastors.
Several closely interrelated questions steer my inquiry: In colonial India, what idioms were available for lambasting religious authority, and what were the cultural valences of those idioms? When did Indians adapt British rhetorical strategies for delegitimizing religious authority, and in doing so how did they signal their critical distance from the ideologies of empire? Finally, what were the effects of the colonialera assault on sacerdotal authority? What forms of subjectivity and sociality did it open, and what forms did it foreclose?
This introduction lays the theoretical groundwork for the inquiry, while subsequent chapters pursue it by way of specific historical conjunctures. A summary of those chapters can be found below. As for the introduction, it delineates several interlocking vectors of analysis. First, it locates my genealogy of priestcraft within the scholarly literature on genealogy of religion and the powers of the secular modern; I argue for the importance of contrapuntal or interactional analysis in studying the intersections of religion, secularism, and colonialism. Next, I consider how priestcraft functions as an idiom of interreligious polemic. I describe the culture of religious controversy that prevailed in colonial India; and, drawing on critical work by Wilfred Cantwell Smith and Gauri Viswanathan, I use religious polemic to rethink the problems of the religious outside and the secular public.
The dissertation suggests that it is more helpful to think of modernity as constitutively anticlerical than as constitutively secular or anti-religious. To support this suggestion, the latter part of the introduction begins to develop the concept anticlerical modernity. It first pauses to consider how the appellation Luther of India, often bequeathed on subcontinental skeptics by Anglophone writers, organizes anticlerical modernity under the sovereign sign of Europe. Following Dipesh Chakrabarty, I set out not to ignore the hegemony of European models, but to use colonial margins to rethink those models normative claims. Next, I turn to the genealogy of priestcraft in Britain, offering a thumbnail sketch of a history treated in greater detail in Chapter 1. Here, drawing on work by Mark Goldie, Justin Champion, and others, I simply want to suggest that secular modernity s war on religion might better be understood as a war on priestcraft and sacerdotalism. Finally, I return to the question of doubt and belief. I distinguish between propositional belief and relational belief, elaborating the latter concept mostly by way of Jacques Derrida s meditations on the fiduciary. As Derrida explains, the web of human relations that constitutes humans as subjects also immerses them in an irreducible field of intersubjective trust -in short, and contra the young Marx, Derrida implies that the human condition will always require, if not illusion, then at least a faith that exceeds empirical knowledge.
In Genealogies of Religion (1993), Talal Asad excavates the conceptual geology of religion in the West and considers the implications of this geology for the rest of the world.5 According to Asad, religion is a culturally provincial term with a distinct
5 Talal Asad, Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianity and Islam (Baltimore: The
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993), 1. For other genealogies of religion, see Wilfred Cantwell Smith,
The Meaning and End of Religion: A New Approach to the Religious Traditions of Mankind (New York: Macmillan, 1963); Jonathan Z. Smith, Imagining Religion: From Babylon to Jonestown (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1982); Peter Harrison, Religion and the Religions in the English Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990); Tomoko Masuzawa, In Search of Dreamtime: The Quest for the Origin of Religion
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993); S. N. Balagangadhara, The Heathen in his Blindness : Asia, the
West, and the Dynamic of Religion (Leiden: Brill, 1994); David Chidester, Savage Systems: Colonialism and
Comparative Religion in Southern Africa (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1996); Russell
McCutcheon, Manufacturing Religion: The Discourse on Sui Generis Religion and the Politics of Nostalgia (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); Richard King, Orientalism and Religion: Postcolonial Theory, India, and the Mystic East (London: Routledge, 1999); Timothy Fitzgerald, The Ideology of Religious Studies (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000); Hans Kippenberg, Discovering Religious History in the Modern Age, trans.
Barbara Harshav (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002); Daniel Dubuisson, The Western
Construction of Religion: Myths, Knowledge, and Ideology, trans. William Sayers (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins
University Press, 2003); Randall Styers, Making Magic: Religion, Magic, and Science in the Modern World (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2004); Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions, or, How European Universalism was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005); and
Timothy Fitzgerald, Discourse on Civility and Barbarity: A Critical History of Religion and Related Categories (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2007). Alongside this substantial body of research unsettling the concept
religion, other scholars have recently sought to redefine the term. For compelling recent efforts, see Thomas A. Tweed, Crossing and Dwelling: A Theory of Religion (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006) and Mark C. Taylor, After God (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007).
history. It assumed its present shape in the North Atlantic world during the early modern period and was then forcibly exported to other locales as part of the imperial expansion of Europe. Asad and other genealogists of religion, operating within a broadly Foucaultian paradigm, have sought to unsettle the concept religion by uncovering its secreted histories.[5] As Tomoko Masuzawa explains, such a project looks to deny the concept the kind of overwhelming sense of objective reality, concrete facticity, and utter self-evidence that now holds us in its sway. [6] Most importantly, it resists the structural separation of religion from power. [7] Genealogists like Asad and Masuzawa reveal just how political religion has always been and never more so than when presented as worldly power s opposite or antidote.
My dissertation joins the general effort to think beyond the concept religion.[8] Like much of the existing scholarship, I draw particular attention to the intersections of religion and colonialism.[9] Imperial ideology made regular use of religion to bolster its rhetoric of civilizational difference. The word religion articulates its sanctity in opposition to a shifting series of profane antonyms (superstition, heathenism, paganism, demonism, the secular). Like so many binaries (male/female, adult/child),
these oppositional pairs came to code the ideological divide separating colonizer from colonized.[10] In the case of religion, however, this binary code proved unstable because of religion s own denotative volatility. Although the British often contrasted their true religion with Indian superstition, they also frequently relegated religion to India while claiming secularism for themselves. In other words, because imperial Britain had not decided what it wanted to be (Anglican or Dissenting, religious or secular), it could not effectively police the line differentiating itself from India. Religion, precisely because it was a confused cultural domain, thus emerged as a particularly generative site for re-imagining colonial borderlines.
It now seems fair to say that the concept religion as we know it has always already implied the secular as its most definitive antonym. As Masuzawa puts it, when religion came to be identified as such, it was already in the process of disappearing, or least of becoming circumscribed in such a way that it was finally discernible as a distinct, and limited, phenomenon. [11] As I will demonstrate, notions of religious imposture have been central to this modern circumscription of the sacred and, as a consequence, to the constitution of cultural modernity as such. For, as Janet R. Jakobsen and Ann Pellegrini have recently argued, the mutual determination of the religious and the secular has taken placed not only in modernity, but, indeed, as modernity. [12] Taking this insight to heart, I will for the sake of brevity generally use the phrase secular modernity to indicate the complex mutual determinations of religion and secularism. The overarching logic of the secular has, after all, typically defined and subsumed the much more tightly delimited category religion.
A monumental scholarship now attests to the failure of the secularization thesis to account for the empirical and theoretical complexities of religious modernity and of secularism itself. If the Iranian Revolution of 1979 was the bellwether of public religion s resurgence, the increased prominence of political religion since the 1980s has cemented the sociological consensus that public religion is here to stay.[13][14] The empirical persistence of religion has been one of several factors prompting scholars to rethink the conceptual bases of secularism. Philosophers working in the Western tradition have, like Charles Taylor and Marcel Gauchet, come to emphasize how Christian and Jewish contestations over the place of the transcendent prepared the way for secularism and its immanent frame. [15] Postcolonial critics like Talal Asad have likewise insisted that despite its ostensible neutrality, secularism continues to bear the stain of the sacred, a fact that partly explains why a Western secularism born of
Christianity has fumbled in its dealings with Islam.[16]
The complex legacy of Western secularism has been debated with particular acuity in the Indian context. In the 1980s, intellectuals like Ashis Nandy and T.N. Madan disavowed secularism because, as they argued, it had been imposed on India by Britain. In the postcolonial period, the imperial ideology had continued to exacerbate class divisions, to centralize state power, and to suppress indigenous modes of folk tolerance. [17] Calls for a reappraisal of secularism became more intense after the rise of the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP), the 1992 destruction of the Babri Mosque in Ayodhya, and, more recently, the 2002 pogroms in Gujarat.[18] Although later commentators have been much less inclined to renounce secularism entirely, they remain committed to critically and creatively refiguring its core concepts and its cultural allegiances.
One of the most persistent problems posed by the interdisciplinary reappraisal of secularism is the problem of cultural origin. If secularism is understood as fundamentally Christian or Western, postcolonial critics concerned with the legacies of imperialism will only be able to adopt it with great ambivalence. Accordingly, two major techniques have been developed for claiming secularism away from the postChristian West. First, some scholars have sought to reterritorialize secularism by insisting that its core values (democratic argumentation, skepticism, empiricism) have been just as pervasive in India as in Europe. Amartya Sen s essays on the
argumentative Indian for instance showcase pre-modern events that, he avers, prove India an epigone of proto-secularist debate.[19] A second group of scholars has sought, more radically, to deprive secularism of any national territory by locating its origins in the contact zones of colonial encounter. Because it is historically and epistemologically prior to both India and the West, the scene of colonial encounter undermines both these integral cultural entities.
Many of the critics who look to colonialism to unmoor secularism from national geography take their theoretical model from Edward Said. His contrapuntal analysis resisted insularity and provincialism by indicating the degree to which empire foisted global connections on even the most local modes of knowledge.[20] This certainly holds true for the major discursive nodes of secular modernity. As Peter van der Veer has argued, in order to track the emergence of concepts like secularity, liberty, and equality, scholars must engage in an interactional history that places colony and metropole in a single frame of reference.[21] Gauri Viswanathan s influential study of British literary education in India exemplifies this type of analysis. As she demonstrates, the British hit upon literary education as a means of improving the moral character of colonial subjects for whom Christian pedagogy (still the preferred method for educating the British working classes) was thought inappropriate. The English literary canon thus hails from India, its secularity a response to the constraints of colonial governance.[22] Contrapuntal analysis also suggests that the legal status of religious minorities in Victorian Britain was redefined, not due to domestic pressures alone, but as part of a colonial conversation about the nature of citizenship.[23] Although contrapuntalism has mostly been used to draw out the cultural contingencies of British and French colonialisms, one could also in principle adapt the method to analyze other contact zones.[24]
Colonial fault-lines thus splinter the study of secularism. But this is not all. As Talal Asad has suggested, because the secular is so much a part of our modern life, it is not easy to grasp it directly ; instead, it must be studied by its shadows, as it were. [25] The critical reappraisal of secularism should proceed, not by hunting the entity
secularism, but by enumerating and interrogating that entity s component parts
(tolerance, progress, liberty, democracy, public sphere, reason, etc).[26] In my estimation, the trope of priestly imposture should be included on this list.27 In order to appreciate the trope s resonance, however, we first need to understand the polemic field in which it was honed and deployed.
Wilfred Cantwell Smith has argued that the modern concept religion emerged through a dialectic process of polemics and apologetics. Smith charts a general movement away from religion as piety toward religions as reified systems of belief and practice. Where the former mode of religiosity emphasized disciplined work upon the self, the latter fixated on doctrinal and communal boundaries, apprehending religion primarily as an object of knowledge rather than as the habitation of the knowing subject.
According to Smith, polemic encounters triggered this historic shift. One s own religion may be piety and faith, obedience, worship, and a vision of God. But one inevitably apprehends an alien religion from the outside, rendering it as an abstract and impersonal pattern of observables. During a debate, the critic presents his opponent s religion schematically in the terms of this abstract pattern. In order to
Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006); Jacques Derrida, Hostipitality, in Acts of Religion, ed. Gil Anijdar (New York: Routledge, 2002), 356-420.
27 For histories of the imposture theory, see Frank Manuel, The Eighteenth Century Confronts the Gods
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1959); Peter Harrison, Religion and the Religions in the English
Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Justin Champion, The Pillars of Priestcraft
Shaken: The Church of England and its Enemies, 1660-1730 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992); Justin Champion, Religion s Safe, with Priestcraft is the War: Augustan Anticlericalism and the Legacy of the English Revolution, 1660-1720, The European Legacy 5.4 (2000): 547-561; and Leigh Eric Schmidt, Hearing Things: Religion, Illusion, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
respond, the religious insider comes to inhabit his opponent s argument. He is forced, in a sense, to step outside of his religion in order to defend it; and, in the process, he alters his relation to pious praxis. What had functioned as the unconscious substrate to subjectivity becomes newly available as an objectified entity that stands over and against the self. Although the insider might return to the fold at debate s end, once he has inhabited his opponent s position, he inevitably carries the outside with him into the interior of belief. There it begins to transform religion from the inside out. [27]
Religion as we know is the product of this process. It is always apprehended externally as a reified object of knowledge that stands apart from the knowing subject. As Smith suggests, this is true for both insiders and outsiders : theologians and anthropologists are not, after all, so very different from one another in their efforts to fix and define idealized religious systems. Of course, even in modern English the older sense of religion as ethical praxis persists, as in the statement Wilfred is more religious than he used to be. Religious interiorities continue to function; it is just that they cannot be disentangled from religious exteriorities. In fact, as Smith summarizes, four distinct senses of religion with four distinct histories continue to cohabit within the word, splitting it from the inside.[28]
The upshot of Smith s dialectic model of religious consciousness is this: modern
religion implicates human subjects in a convoluted infolding of the irreligious outside.
If we take Smith s argument seriously, it becomes impossible to sustain a na ve notion of the insider s perspective in matters of religion. As soon as anyone steps forward to offer her perspective as an insider, she has already assumed the schematic imperatives of the externalist position. Brian Massumi s thoughts on subjectivation are apposite here. He maintains that there is no such thing as interiority in the sense of a closed, self-reflective system. Rather, [t]here is only a multileveled infolding of an aleatory outside, with which the infolding remains in contact. Despite the occasional coalescence of more rigid boundaries between self and other, the cordoning off is never complete. [29] Smith s rereading of religion through the scene of polemic encounter suggests something very similar in its refusal of uncontaminated interiority. Although Smith does wax nostalgic for the authentic pieties of an earlier age, his theoretical model exceeds his quest for religious origins. Above all else, Smith s historicist account of religion s dialectical emergence signals the productivity of polemical misrecognition. He locates religion not in the pious interiority of belief, but in the slippery inter-subjective space in which belief can be communicated and, in its communication, isolated, identified, and catalogued precisely as belief.
Smith s focus on polemical, oppositional religion echoes Gauri Viswanathan s recent call for scholars to rethink secularism through the framework of heterodoxy. Viswanathan suggests that to overemphasize the contest between religion and secular reason (as modern meta-narratives are wont to do) is to homogenize religion by effacing the violent forms of dissent that have littered its history. One might, she implies, fracture the grand conflict between religion and reason by granting more attention to religion as an oppositional knowledge system ; such an approach, she hopes, may provide for a more expansive idea of secularism. [30] While Viswanathan uses the frame of heterodoxy to rethink the prehistory of secularism, her method lends itself just as well to remapping the critical spaces of secular modernity. Where secularism posits a single space categorically outside of religion, heterodoxy provides for convoluted inter-foldings of the religious with the irreligious. A public sphere structured by oppositional heterodoxies operates kaleidoscopically, its shifting critical spaces positioned inside some religious formations and outside of others. It denies secular criticism its ostensible transcendence of belief, maintaining instead that all critical positions inhabit a single immanent plane. Critical insight is gained not through transcendence of religion, but through a lateral shift in oppositional location.
This theoretical model helps to clarify the scene of religious controversy in colonial India. The colonial state typically asserted its superiority to Indian civil society by claiming that, as a secular agent, it stood above the oppositional heterodoxies of Indian religions (see Chapter 3). In the colonial context, then, to deny secularism its critical transcendence of religious belief is to resist the British state s claim to stand above its Indian subjects. Revaluing heterodoxy also allows us to revisit practices of interreligious polemic in colonial India. As a rich and growing historical scholarship has demonstrated, religious controversy was of central importance to colonial public culture. For heuristic purposes, one might follow Kenneth Jones in classifying these controversies as either internal or external in scope and audience. The former, helmed by reformers intent on revising received orthodoxies, took place within a single tradition; the latter, often initiated by missionaries or aggressive new religious movements, took place between different religions. As Jones suggests, in the twentieth century these two types of disputation were joined by purely secular ideologies once again altered the field of religious debate.32
These categorical divisions, although useful, do of course oversimplify the shifting scene of religious controversy in colonial India. During the nineteenth century, new religious movements proliferated at a dizzying pace, and the devotional positions that they championed confounded older rubrics for configuring community.33 Although these religious did articulate the identity politics of religious communalism, they also did much more. Indeed, to focus too insistently on the communalist telos of nineteenth century religious movements is to ignore the confusions of identity that prevailed at the time.
Religious debate and competition took many forms, including formal addresses, organized debates, and street preaching; the publication of journals, pamphlets, books, tracts, and translated scriptures in English and the vernaculars; religious processions and performances; the production of visual artifacts (especially in new hybrid forms like the chromolithograph and Kalighat painting); street theatre; rumor and gossip;
32 Kenneth W. Jones, Preface, in Religious Controversy in British India: Dialogues in South Asian Languages, ed. Kenneth W. Jones (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), ix.
33 For general overviews of religious reform movements in colonial India, see John Nichol Farquhar,
Modern Religious Movements in India (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1977 [1914]); Kenneth W. Jones, Socio-religious Reform Movements in British India (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Antony Copley, ed., Gurus and their Followers: New Religious Reform Movements in Colonial India (New Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 2000); Gwilym Beckerlegge, ed., Colonialism, Modernity, and Religious Identities:
Religious Reform Movements in South Asia (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2008).
voluntary associations; new and old educational institutions; and, last but not least, the theatrical venues provided by the colonial state itself (e.g. the courts). Some of these practices and structures drew on classical precedent, whether Islamicate or Sanskritic (e.g. the debating protocols of munazara and sh"str"rth).[31] Others were new to the nineteenth century. In any case, it was the interconnection of these divergent objects, practices, and performance venues that constituted the colonial public, whether construed (following J rgen Habermas) as a public sphere or (following Sandria
Freitag) as a public arena. [32]
Print was arguably the most important of these overlapping public venues. While the printing press had been introduced to India in the sixteenth century, it did not take off until the nineteenth, when it became central to public contestations over religion.[33] The growing pervasiveness of print during this period had several effects. First, it facilitated the rise of the regional vernaculars, which asserted their independence from Sanskrit, Arabic, Persian, and English by developing new literary forms (especially prose essays and novels) and by developing procedures for systematizing their grammars and regulating their vocabularies. This would have a substantial effect on the formation of religious communities, as demonstrated most dramatically by the political bifurcation of Hindustani into Hindi and Urdu. Second, print capitalism cut across the regional vernaculars to facilitate the formation of global identities, whether communalistic, nationalistic, or cosmopolitan.[34]
Third, print media encouraged lateral solidarities that undermined the traditional hierarchical structures of religious authority. Although I will reconsider this claim in Chapter 2, (situating it within what Michael Warner has called the WhigMcLuhanite model of print media effects), the basic argument bears stating here: as sacred texts that were once the preserve of trained elites were disseminated via print, charisma was channeled out of the person and onto the printed page. [35] A new breed of lay leader came to predominate in the new milieu. As Barbara Metcalf has suggested, these lay leaders turned from an esoteric style of pedagogy based on the personal relationship between teacher and student to a public and impersonal pedagogy rooted in schools, journalism, street preaching, and (perhaps mostly importantly) the printed book. Like the print artifacts they plied, these men were supremely mobile, both in their peripatetic lifestyles and in their double access to traditional and colonial
forms of knowledge. They were most at home in urban settings, where other unmoored subjects welcomed the new identities and new social networks proffered by voluntary religious associations.[36]
Fourth,
and finally: as the above discussion suggests, print culture redrew the line
between public and private in colonial South Asia, often interlacing the
two quite vertiginously.[37] Print artifacts founded their public
on readerly solitude, although this solitude was often complicated by the
common practice of reading newspapers aloud in places like teashops. They
circulated anonymously and, in principle, infinitely to convene an eerily
immaterial public, the only concrete manifestations of which were the metonymic
pages of print artifacts themselves.[38] Print media were, moreover, of central
importance to the closeted political project that, according to Partha
Chatterjee, gave rise to anti-colonial nationalism.[39]
The domain of spiritual sovereignty demarcated and defended by elites in
Bengal relied heavily on the literary
genres of the print vernacular; importantly, these included women s journals designed to render domestic space a suitable site for inventing the nation.[40]
In sum, the scholarship on religious controversy in colonial India echoes an increasingly common sentiment: far from inculcating blind belief or meditative passivity, religion in South Asia has long provided for the pleasures of argument.[41] These pleasures are aptly illustrated by anecdote recorded by the Rev. Bowley, some six years after his intervention at the banyan tree. A prince of Benares who was fond of discussions once invited a dozen men to his palace to debate religion. His guests included not only Bowley, but also several maulvis and even a professed atheist armed with a Bible. As Bowley tells it, most of the participants thoroughly enjoyed their urbane disputation. Graciously accommodating others beliefs, the atheist even joined in prayers later on in the evening. Bowley, however, was disgruntled. The maulvis were rude and unbecoming when told that Christians do not pretend to comprehend the mysterious doctrine of the Trinity; still worse, they insisted on discussing Jesus circumcision. Although the prince continued to hold his debates, the Reverend declined future invitations.[42]
The pleasures and forms of religious argument in colonial India were, assuredly, many. People debated religion in different media and different languages and for different reasons. It is notable, then, that Anglophone commentators on the culture of religious controversy consistently sought to fit anticlerical polemic to a single historic pattern. At one point or another, almost every reformer of note was hailed as the Luther of India. This moniker was foisted on ancient and modern religious critics, from the Buddha to Kabir to Ram Mohan Roy. In the chapters to follow, we will see journalist Karsandas Mulji, much to the chagrin of the prosecuting attorneys for the Maharaj Libel Case, represented as a Reformer, a Martin Luther of the Banian caste (Chapter 3).[43] We will also encounter Sw!m$ Day!nand Saraswat$, who for many remains the quintessential Indian Luther (Chapter 4).
Day!nand earned this appellation early on. For instance, in his 1879 address to the Meerut chapter of the %rya Sam!j, Henry Steel Olcott proclaimed the Swami the Luther of Modern India. In India, as Olcott explains, the mighty mass of people persists in an enchanted state, blindly follow[ing] the lead of a debauched, ignorant, selfish priesthood. Dayanand, not only a Luther, but also a new Gautama, has begun to regenerate and redeem them. His enlightened followers in the Arya Samaj should take it as their first duty to assist him. [44] In his speech, Olcott assembles a series of religious critics (Dayanand, Gautama, Zarathustra, Pythagoras) and collates them under the sign of Luther, totem of Protestant modernity. Here, as elsewhere, Luther is made the inescapable referent of all anticlerical protest.
This phenomenon fits a familiar pattern. As Dipesh Chakrabarty has influentially argued, Europe remains the sovereign, theoretical subject of all histories, including the ones we call Indian, Chinese, Kenyan, and so on. [45] Because European modernity is paradigmatic for social theory, it remains the silent referent of non-Western histories that become historical precisely through the application of Western thought; non-Western history thus re-inscribes the colonial relationship in the very categories of its analysis. In Chakrabarty s estimation, however, the solution to this problem does not lie in rejecting or discarding European thought. His prescription is far more ambivalent: European thought is at once both indispensible and inadequate in helping us to think through the experiences of political modernity in non-Western nations, and provincializing Europe becomes the task of exploring how this thought which is now everybody s heritage and which affects us all may be renewed from and for the margins. [46]
The impasses of Europe s theoretical sovereignty have shaped debates about postcolonial secularism. Although Western secularism has been nothing if not uneven and heterogeneous (e.g. the Church of England vs. French la cit ), it has tended to present a unified front to the postcolonial world. Postcolonial Indian secularism inevitably departs from the idealized Western model, and can thus seem derivative or tragically inadequate.[47] Some intellectuals, like Ashis Nandy, responded to this impasse by rejecting secularism. Others, like Amartya Sen, have sought to deny secularism its Western-ness by identifying proto-secularist moments in pre-modern India. Sen champions Akbar as a pre-modern paragon of secularist values. Akbar predates not only the British Empire, but all of European modernity; as Sen points out, when Akbar was preaching tolerance in Agra, the West was still embroiled in the Inquisition. Sen, to be sure, has a point. In the terms of his argument, however, Akbar can be secular only insofar as he meets norms set by Western social theory, here represented by John Rawls and J rgen Habermas. In Sen s essays, argumentative reason always refers, and not all that silently, to the modern West.[48]
Rather than universalizing and de-historicizing the values of secular modernity, one might instead return them to their colonial contexts in order, as Chakrabarty prescribes, to revise them from the margins. Such an approach would foreground what
Sumathi Ramaswamy has called the off-modern or what, to suit the present context, I would term the off-secular (see Conclusion).[49] I think that anticlerical modernity is just such an off-secular concept. It addresses canonical texts in the making of secular modernity, but refuses to divorce these texts from their religious forbearers and contemporaries (Chapter 1). The dissertation aims to track how anticlerical modernity, as fashioned in Europe, came to be rethought from the colonial margins margins that are read more readily as modern, I would add, if we allow the anticlerical to displace the secular.
Thus, in the case of India s proliferating Luthers, the trick is to recognize that anticlerical connection (e.g. Luther-Dayanand) as both indispensible and inadequate. It is indispensible because European modernity, anticlerical or otherwise, remains hegemonic, and so in order for India to be read as modern it must be read in relation to Europe. It is inadequate not only because the sign Luther fails as a rubric for coding the richly diverse skeptical attitudes of colonial India, but also because its explanatory power, even in Europe, has often been overstated. The challenge is thus to read colonial pairings like Luther-Dayanand contrapuntally, using each term to refigure the other Luther shapes our perception of Dayanand, and Dayanand our perception of Luther. The task, in other words, is to use the colonial margins to rethink the stakes of our shared modernity.
In Hind Swaraj (1908), M. K. Gandhi exploited the trope of priestly imposture for rhetorical effect. His fictive interlocutor accuses the charismatic Gandhi of
encouraging religious charlatanism. Many a cheat has by talking in a similar strain led the people astray. Gandhi responds by confirming that all religions may have some humbug about them, but he is prepared to maintain that humbugs in worldly matters are far worse than the humbugs in religion. The real humbug, as Gandhi aims to prove, is the humbug of civilization, and in order to expose this humbug, India must appreciat[e] and conserv[e] its religions for only religion can ground opposition to colonial capitalism and technocratic reason.[50] Here Gandhi inverts the trope of imposture. Where imperial ideology had denounced the humbug of Hinduism, Gandhi denounces the humbug of empire revealing it to be precisely ideological, a political illusion, insofar as it assumes the role of the religious charlatan. In the following brief genealogy of priestcraft, I will suggest that Gandhi s inversion of imposture replicates in miniature the history of anticlerical invective, from Luther to Marx. The sedimented stages of this history continued to animate the imposture theory in 1908, and, as Gandhi demonstrates, their critical contiguity could be exploited to good effect.
The modern West s obsession with priestly imposture may have begun with Protestants suspicions about the ill deeds of the Catholic clerisy. But the polemic force of the imposture narrative quickly outstripped its original purpose. If the rhetoric of priestcraft had been devised to reform Christianity by cleansing it of its clerical excesses, the same rhetoric would ultimately provide Enlightenment critics with a surefire strategy for dismissing Christianity entirely. Starting in the 1680s, a flurry of English and French treatises broadened the scope of the imposture theory to suggest that all religion might be understood as a fraud perpetrated on the world by the priestly class. Most of these critics wanted to do away with priestly religion so as to restore whatever philosophical creed they thought had preceded it (Deism, Spinozism). But full-fledged atheism was soon to follow. Indeed, several scholars have suggested that the priestcraft narrative provided Karl Marx with the conceptual apparatus for his theory of ideology. Religion, as Marx well knew, was ideology s prototype: only by exposing both secular and sacred frauds can humanity at last discover the hard facts of the material world. To trace the history of the discursive object priestcraft is thus to trace how secular modernity s most potent epistemological procedures emerged from the Christian cultures that preceded and produced them.
According to the Oxford English Dictionary, priestcraft in its earliest uses (c. 1483) simply referred to the knowledge, training, or work of a priest; the exercise of priestly functions. This original sense became obsolete, however, as priestcraft (from about 1680) began to denote something much more nefarious: the maintenance or extension of priestly power and influence; the practices and policy supporting this; priestly scheming, guile, or deceit. The new sense of priestcraft maintained the emphasis on outward performance, but transfigured that performance s inner motivation. Piety became hypocrisy, and the inscrutable inner life of the skilled priest prodded fantasies of diabolical deceit. Eventually this would result in a paranoid polemics obsessed with the execrable deeds of conniving clerics.
According to Mark Goldie, Protestants anticlerical and anti-Catholic jibes swelled to produce the radical anticlericalism of the Enlightenment. As Goldie puts it, as a habit of mind anticlerical suspicion became omnivorous and devoured its own children. [51] An infamous early pioneer of this expanded anticlericalism was the anonymous Trait des Trois Imposteurs (c.1719), which scandalously imputed imposture to Moses, Jesus, and Mohammad, renouncing all revealed religion in favor of Spinozist pantheism. In its frontispiece, the treatise depicted all three prophets in partial exposure, masks dangling in their hands.[52] Translations from Greek and Latin provided crucial fodder for Enlightenment disquisitions on priestly fraud hungry to expand their narrative repertoire. Particularly important was Lucian s The Religious Imposter, or, the Life of Alexander, a Sham Prophet, Doctor, and Fortune Teller. Equipped with a baby snake, a purple cape, and a prosthetic head, Alexander used his theatrical wiles to convince the credulous residents of a little town that he was an emissary of the god Aesculapius. Enlightenment writers took Alexander s exploits as paradigmatic. As the text s English translator quipped, such has been the artifice of corrupt Priesthood in all Ages and Countries. [53] All-out atheism was soon to follow.
As Goldie has it, Karl Marx took up the anticlerical modernity articulated by Enlightenment critics of religion, borrowing the conceptual apparatus of priestcraft to formulate his theory of ideology. Marx himself, after all, said more or less the same thing: the criticism of religion, as he so famously announced, is the premise of all criticism.57 Goldie helpfully summarizes the core elements of all the narratives of priestly imposture enumerated above. Ignorance and falsehood are the instruments of men of power ; these men rule by fabricating illusions ; and these illusions clothe naked power with their icons and idols. To liberate the duped masses, the skeptical few must unmask this cadre of dastardly deceivers. One of the foremost mythologies of enlightened modernity, the imposture theory demonstrates that Enlightenment, for all its own claims, was not radically disjunctive from the Protestant critique of popery. 58 Justin Champion goes still farther in questioning modernity s secularist teleology. He insists that early modern anticlericalism not be interpreted as proleptic of Enlightenment irreligion. Resisting such anachronism through insistent returns to the topsy-turvy heterodoxies of the seventeenth-century, Champion is able to reframe the core conflict around religion in modernity. Secular modernity emerged not in
57 Goldie s suggestion that priestcraft and ideology are genealogically intertwined poses serious methodological problems for scholars involved in the ideological critique of religion. Put bluntly, to say that religion is ideological is to frame a tautology. Religion is the prototype for ideology, not an instance of it. It is well beyond the scope of this dissertation to think through the implications of this claim, but its pertinence to contemporary debates in religious studies bears noting. In general, I would suggest that we replace the question Is religion ideological? with the question How do the contiguous concepts religion and ideology constrain how we imagine belief? A thorough answer to this question would also take into account Simon During s recent research into secular magic. During documents the rise of magic as an entertainment industry in parodic relation to authentic hierophants; he goes on to demonstrate how, around the turn of the twentieth century, professional magicians like George M li s migrated into the cinema and other emergent culture industries. If twentieth century contests between media magicians and ideological critics seemed to replicate the primal drama of priestly exposure, this is, one might surmise, no coincidence: by During s account, magic mediates between religion and culture. Simon During, Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2002); see also Randall Styers, Making Magic: Religion, Magic, and Science in the Modern World (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002). For an account of how notions of ideology are used in recent work in religious studies, see Tylor Roberts, Rhetorics of Ideology and Criticism in the Study of Religion, Journal of Religion 85.3 (2005): 367-389; Gary Lease, Ideology, in Guide to the Study of
Religion, ed. Willi Braun and Russell McCutcheon (London: Cassell, 2000), 441. For fuller histories of ideology, see Terry Eagleton, Ideology: An Introduction (London: Verso, 1991) and Slavoj &i ek, ed., Mapping Ideology (London: Verso, 1994).
58 Goldie, Ideology, 270
opposition to religion, but rather in opposition to the notion of sacerdos. [54] Or, as John
Toland put it: religion s safe, with priestcraft is the war.
My dissertation tries to carry this critical insight into the nineteenth century, highlighting critics of religion generally sidelined by the history of secularism (e.g. William Howitt s Popular History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (1833)). My aim is not to displace secularism entirely, but to insist that it be read alongside anticlericalism:
Howitt and Marx.
Before bringing this introduction to a close, I would like to call attention to one final feature of anticlerical modernity: it is more invested in relational belief than in propositional belief. As Donald Lopez has noted, modern scholars of religion have often taken belief as their primary field of study, reducing religion to abstract theological propositions of the sort one might find in a catechism.[55] This doctrinal fixation, as Wilfred Cantwell Smith observed, tends to reify religion by abstracting it from its social networks and its embodied practices. Such abstraction has served many functions, including the production of bureaucratic religions readily arrogated to the managerial apparatus of colonial states (see Chapter 3). In general, however, it tends to distract from relational belief, or trust in persons. In comparison, anticlerical polemic has paid very little attention to propositional particularities. Its chief concern, however scandalous, is with personalities its gleefully ad hominem attacks on clerics having attracted rather more gossips and politicians than philologists or theologians. Anticlerical modernity is, in short, a rift in the fabric of relational belief, a standing challenge to the loving trust that binds the disciple to priest or guru.
Jacques Derrida has described this as the fiduciary order of modernity. As he explains, the Enlightenment, even at its most critical and rational, must always suppose trustworthiness. The social body is founded on an irreducible faith that unfolds from the testimonial nature of all speech acts, including and perhaps especially speech acts that vouch for scientific truth ( I promise to tell you the truth beyond all proof and all theoretical demonstration, believe me, etc. ). Techno-scientific rationality, like all other forms of utterance, relies on this fundamental communicative trust. In Derrida s words, it always brings into play and confirms the fiduciary credit of an elementary faith which is, at least in its essence or calling, religious. By this account, the religious is the supplementary outside that is the founding condition for the secular. Secular rationality can intervene in the fiduciary structure of the social body, restructuring the religious, but it can never eliminate faith entirely.[56]
Were all traces of faith to be abolished, society would collapse. In the words of one early nineteenth century writer, a certain extent of credulity, or, more properly, belief, may, indeed, be considered as absolutely necessary to the well-being of social communities; for universal skepticism would be universal distrust. [57] If our collective credulity involves us in collective illusion, so be it. Indeed to exit entirely from collective illusion would be to court psychosis. This, as &i ek has explained, is why the non-duped err: the only way not to be deceived is to maintain a distance toward the symbolic order, i.e. to assume a psychotic position a psychotic is precisely a subject who is not duped by the symbolic order. But the psychotic, in his pervasive paranoia, falls into the classic error of ideological thought, fabricating a vision of an undeceived subject who holds and manipulates the threads of the deception proper to the symbolic order. The non-duped subject thus errs because he is, however ironically, too easy of belief. [58] As &i ek and others have argued, there is no pure outside to delusion: the claim to exodus from ideology is ideology par excellence.[59]
Here the priestly specter returns as an uncanny apparition, which haunts the suspicious science of ideological critique and marks its limit. In the 1930s, Karl
Mannheim tried to differentiate the scientific criticism of ideology from mere distrust and suspicion. Where the na f holds individuals personally responsible for the deceptions that we detect in their utterances, the scientific critic locates deception in social structures.[60] &i ek suggests that the spectral Big Other remains lodged in the phantasmatic heart of modernity, the irrational animus of its hermeneutics of suspicion. (The tension between structural and personal deception will be played out in a very different idiom in Chapter 4, where Swami Dayananda Saraswati rereads "a#kar!c!rya s metaphysics of m!y! through an anticlerical lens). For anticlerical modernity, in particular, this figure proves inescapable. How, then, are we to understand the persistence of the charlatan?
One might take up the Derridean notion of the perverformative, as developed by Hent de Vries. As de Vries writes, any religious utterance, act, or gesture, stands in the shadow more or less, but never totally avoidable of perversion, parody or kitsch, of blasphemy and idolatry. [61] The notion of the performative is of course J. L. Austin s. It indicates, as he so famously put it, the sort of utterance that can do things (like I do effects a marriage). As Austin notes, such speech acts will misfire if conditions are infelicitous ( I do does nothing if the bride is absent, or the groom is a bigamist, or the priest is not properly licensed).[62] For Austin such misfires remain incidental to the phenomenon of performativity per se, but for Derrida they are central. Every successful performative is predicated on and shadowed by the possibility of its own failure; as a consequence, the risk of misfire becomes the internal and positive condition and possibility of success, the very force and law of its emergence. Because of this structuring condition, a successful performative is necessarily an impure performative in that it carries within it the trace of its own failure.[63] The neologism perverformative signals this invagination graphemically: perversion splits the performative from the inside.
The etymology of priestcraft offers one paradigmatic instance of the slide of religion into perverse parody. Fairly quickly, a word denoting the expert performance of ritual duties came to denote something very different: the iterability of priests professional performance inscribes the potential for fakery into the sacred rite itself. Trust in the professional competency of the priest is always predicated on the possibility of betrayal and the possibility that the sincere professional is a fraudulent charlatan. Suspicion lurks within trust, just as faith is always already inhabited by an intimation of doubt. One might suggest that the appeal of some charismatic figures derives from their ability to mobilize trust and suspicion at the same time, thereby more fully inhabiting the inherent structure of belief.[64] Indeed, as Simon During has pointed out, the ambiguity of the magician as object of belief places him within the same cultural sphere as some forms of imaginative literature. Imaginative exercises like Samuel Taylor Coleridge s suspension of disbelief model a mixture of faith and doubt, central to the powers of the charlatan.[65]
As I will suggest in Chapter 5, the Theosophical Society experimented with just such an adumbrated belief. Its occultism took priestcraft as its starting point, but sought to rethink the imposture theory of religion. For instance, one 1884 article avers that all the different religious systems of the world have suffered from priestly corruption. Only in the modern period has the West awakened from its nightmare to find out that it has been led by the nose by the priests. A problem, however, remains for the Theosophical writer. Why did so much of humanity fall for the lie? [I]f all these theological fables are nothing else but stupid tales, at the absurdity of which a child would laugh, how could they dominate for so many centuries the minds of the people? Because, as the Theosophists have it, every religious lie conceals a secret doctrine that the masses intuitively perceived. [66] Theosophical wisdom suggests the inverse of Derrida s perverformative: secreted within ersatz religion abides a kernel of irreducible truth.
In what follows, I will consider how religious fraud was theorized under conditions of empire. Chapters 1 and 2, relatively broad in scope, chart the genealogy of priestcraft from the English Enlightenment to British India; despite considerable temporal latitude, their primary mooring is in the period from 1813-1840. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 consider how the discourse of priestly imposture articulated during this earlier period was revived during a later moment of religious reform (1858-1885). Each chapter analyzes a specific discursive conjuncture: two offer micro-historical accounts of religious scandals; one interprets a modern religious text. My conclusion returns to the general problematic of secularism, criticism, and the fiduciary.
Chapter 1, The History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations, takes its title from the text that is its principle topic: Quaker litterateur William Howitt s Popular
History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (1833). In the chapter, I suggest that Howitt situates his text within two English anticlerical lineages. First, under the sign of George Fox, he raises the ghost of seventeenth-century Christian heterodoxy. Second, under the sign of Charles Blount, he revives critical deism and, albeit in attenuated form, the radical Enlightenment. In Howitt s text, these two lineages enter into just the sort of tactical alliance that I have suggested characterizes anticlerical modernity. In addition to parsing Howitt s invocation of the English past, I also return his text to the early 1830s. Starting in 1828, a series of legal reforms had begun to redefine the status of religious minorities in Britain. Howitt, I suggest, wanted to use the ensuing confusion in minority status to return the Quakers to their anticlerical origins; but he found that to tell the story of English priestcraft in 1833, he had first to traverse the world. Due in large part to the stridently anticlerical rhetoric of British Evangelicals since the Charter renewal debates of 1813, the problem of priestcraft had become inextricably intertwined with the problem of empire. It is no coincidence, then, that after completing his History of Priestcraft, Howitt went on to protest the ethical abuses of British colonialism.
Chapter 2, Priestly Despots, expands on this contrapuntal connection by analyzing the conceptual grammar of the imposture theory as redeployed in India. It makes two related arguments. First, as Nicholas Dirks has suggested, in the early part of the nineteenth century British colonialism s mode of governance shifted decisively. The rhetoric of reform remade colonial governmentality by rendering it more diffuse and prodding it to intervene in Indian culture. I suggest that the figure of the despotic priest played an important role in efforts to theorize this new style of colonialism, which, following Michel Foucault, I describe as pastoral power. Once imperial ideologues had identified priestcraft as the eternal substrate of Indian politics, colonial power devised ways to undermine the priests and redeem the souls of the colonized. Second, I argue that print media were central to the colonial effort to institute a new species of pastoral power that would re-form colonial subjects. Print artifacts were situated within a powerful cultural narrative that Michael Warner has described as the Whig-McLuhanite model of print media effects. I locate the lineaments of this model in documents from the period; Anglo-Indian print theorists hoped that rational reading publics would displace fanatic congregational multitudes.
Chapter 3, Guru is God, considers how this cluster of discourses was applied in a scandalous trial of 1862. Intrepid journalist Karsandas Mulji published an article alleging that Jadun!thj$ Brizratanj$, a Maharaj or guru of the Pu()im!rg$ sect of
Vai(*avas, had foisted himself sexually on his devotees; the Maharaj sued him for libel. After months of shocking revelations about the guru s erotic escapades, the trial ended with a ruling in favor of the defendant: the Maharaj was, as alleged, a libidinous imposter. In my discussion of the scandal, I draw on the trial transcript, as well as selections from the English and Gujarati press. I use these documents to contrast the political and devotional order instituted by the court ruling with the utopian ethics implied by the Maharaj s devotional writings. In brief, I argue that colonial power tended to bifurcate Hinduism into a liberal religion, aimed at the governance of the individual soul, and a bureaucratic religion, aimed at the governance of the population. By contrast, the bhakti displaced by the trial enjoined an ethics of self-unmaking, of radical relationality, lateral solidarity, and self-surrender (!tma-nivedan).
Chapter 4, Pur!*ic Popery, turns to a text very much influenced by the Maharaj Libel Case: Sw!m$ Day!nand Saraswat$ s Saty"rth Prak"# (1875). Karsandas Mulji had begun the translation of priestcraft into the North Indian vernaculars; Dayanand finished the job with his Hindi-language monument to Vedic revival. In this text, Dayanand translates priestcraft as pope-l$l!. My chapter analyzes, at length, the hybrid logic of this bilingual compound. First, I argue that the term is central to his double program of Vedic reform and national rejuvenation. By labeling his opponents as popes, Dayanand forces them into semantic exile, refracting heterodoxy through the linguistic codes of the nation. The popes entered India with the fall into debased modernity (that is, the Kali Yug), and the dialectic contest between popish lies and resurgent Vedic truth has propelled history ever since. Second, I use the compound
pope-lila to open the theory of priestly imposture to a different body of thought.
Dayanand is intent on reclaiming the ninth century philosopher "a#kar!c!rya (Shankara) for his reform program; but in order to do so, he must divorce Shankara from his non-dualist metaphysics. This proves no easy feat. I argue that the specter of m!y! haunts Dayanand s book. He constructs the compound pope-lila tendentiously in order to delimit divine illusion by attributing human error to human fraud. The ultimate effect of his effort, however, is to underscore Shankara s cosmic suspicion: illusion is the horizon of the real.
Chapter 5, A Skeptic s Medium, turns from Dayanand to one of his least favorite friends: Madame Helena Petrovna Blavatsky. The chapter analyzes the scandalous Coulomb Affair of 1884-85. I use a range of primary documents to sketch the general contours of the colonial public before which the scandal unfolded. I then consider how Theosophy intervened within the epistemology of exposure that undergirds the trope of priestly imposture. I draw particular attention to how the stereotype of the credulous native constrained the public actions available to Indian Theosophists like Mohini Chatterjee and to how Blavatsky experimented with an epistemology of the veil that simultaneously promised public openness and occult closure. My discussion concludes by defining miracle as an event that refuses to present itself fully in public.
My conclusion synthesizes this genealogy of priestcraft and religious imposture in colonial India. It briefly gestures to the rhetoric of charlatanism after 1885, with particular reference to Gandhi and (in a perverse pairing) Osho. It then returns to some of the general topics broached in this introduction by considering the mutual determinations of secularism, criticism, and belief. I consider the recent effort to recuperate Edward Said s notion of secular criticism for the post-secular age, and I propose an off-secular criticism that uses belief to resist the religious effects of secularist doubt.
Q: What is that men call Religion?
A: A politick cheat put upon the world.
Q: Who were the first contrivers of this cheat?
A: Some cunning men that designed to keep the world in subjection and awe.
-- Charles Wolsey (1669) [67]
A Popular History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (1833) catalogues the basest frauds and the most shameless delusions ever perpetuated under the name of religion. Penned by William Howitt (1792-1879), the book aims to shew that priestcraft in all ages and all nations has been the same; that its nature is one, and that nature essentially evil. [68] To showcase this universal evil, the book ferries its reader from Indian temples to Druid circles, from snowy Siberia to tropical Africa, stopping off along the way in Assyria, Egypt, Scandinavia, Persia, America, and Greece. In the end, however, the book returns home to England to vituperate against that particular nation s established church: in Howitt s hands, universal priestcraft is a tool with an immediate (and much more local) use, designed to be wielded against the ecclesiastical state.
William Howitt had been reared by provincial Quakers who were not pleased with his decision to enter the world of literature. Their opprobrium, however, did not slow his ambitions. After his 1821 marriage to Mary Botham, the two became prolific writers, authoring between them over 180 titles on diverse topics including poetry, natural history, slavery, colonialism, and German and Scandinavian literature. To borrow a phrase from one of their biographers, the Howitts were incomparable Victorian samplers, dabbling in seemingly all major trends of the period; their early poetic Romanticism gave way to strident reformism in the 1830s and, by the 1860s and 1870s, to experimentation with spiritualism and even Catholicism.[69] With their dual commitment to religion and the literary imagination, the Howitts vast oeuvre might prove a promising site for an interrogation of Simon During s claim that, in the nineteenth century, literature came to mediate between religion and belief. [70] That, however, will not be my project here; instead, I will leave the Howitts eclectic sampling behind to analyze William s diatribe against priestcraft.
This chapter aims to thicken the genealogical claims made in the introduction, enumerating the major treatises on religious imposture in order to amplify my inquiry into anticlerical modernity. The chapters to follow will join this history of imposture, diffusing and dispersing it to rethink its ostensible secularity from the colonial margins. As I suggested in the introduction, Howitt s History of Priestcraft gestures to the horizontal scope of the imposture theory of religion. My project seeks, in a sense, to revisit Howitt s book. Where Howitt looked for a universal, static phenomenon, I track a mobile discursive object ( priestcraft ) as it circulated globally under the aegis of empire. Where Howitt rushed to racial origins, mapping global cultures through their arboreal lines of descent, I emphasize the synchronic conjunctures and rhizomatic crossings of colonialism. My project s scope is much more tightly delimited than Howitt s; however, in principle, it gestures beyond cultural areas toward global cultural flows.
This chapter uses Howitt s History of Priestcraft to sketch the itineraries of that term since the late seventeenth century. Howitt was a Quaker, and he wanted to return the Society of Friends to its origins in the strict disestablishmentarianism of George Fox
(1624-1691). Fox s fiery denunciations of the official church pepper the pages of the History of Priestcraft; but as I will suggest, their influence is rivaled by unmarked allusions to Charles Blount (1654-1693), a less devout religious critic of the same period. Fox and Blount represent two poles of England s anticlerical tradition, which (and despite the contemporaneity of the two men) might be figured as Reformation and Enlightenment. Howitt makes easy use of both modalities: doctrinal difference recedes behind polemical commonality. As I suggest, the dual availability of Blount and Fox for Howitt would seem to support an argument framed by historians like Justin
Champion and Mark Goldie. The Enlightenment was not radically disjunctive from the Reformation; especially in England, the two declared a mutual war on priestcraft, together articulating anticlerical modernity.
The chapter goes on to make a further argument: by the 1830s it had become difficult to extricate English anticlericalism from the wider cultural frame of empire. Despite his attempt to reclaim the spirit of the national past, Little England eludes Howitt: he can only come back home after having traversed the world. The referential slide of religious comparison had intensified since the seventeenth century s efforts to identify heathen conformities (discussed below). To trace the history of global priestcraft in 1832 was to come up against two different discursive fields, each of which involved the religious critic in the ideologies of empire. First, the grand comparative disciplines, with their effort to order the world through a decidedly racial logic, provided Howitt with the scholarly skeleton of his global history. Second, Evangelical cries for the moral uplift of the colonies had latched onto priestcraft as the major organizing concept for the denunciation of native culture, particularly Hindoo culture. Accordingly, the central chapter in Howitt s History is the chapter on India, the land where priestcraft was at once in full flower and full fruit; in that state at which it has always aimed, but never, not even in the bloody reign of the Papal church, attained elsewhere (PHP, 74-75). The imbrications of anticlericalism with imperialism led Howitt, after completing the Popular History of Priestcraft, to turn to anti-colonial agitation, a passion that culminated in his book Colonization and Christianity (1838).
The following discussion, then, consists of three sections. The first ( The Quaker Establishment ) interrogates Howitt s legal status as a religious minority. It briefly outlines the lifting of disabilities on minorities that took place after 1828, suggesting that the volatility of minority status during this period led Howitt to reconsider the Quaker s relationship to George Fox and the formative seventeenth century. Howitt tried to recoup the oppositional ethos of Quaker origins, but he also undermined English national history by casting for transnational solidarities: Dissent, in the History of Priestcraft, emerges as a cosmopolitan category.
The next section ( Great is Diana of the Ephesians ) traces the second scion of English anticlericalism invoked by Howitt. This is the longest section in the chapter; it uses Charles Blount to reconstruct the history of the imposture theory of religion since the Enlightenment. The final section of the chapter ( Heathen Conformities ) tracks how early modern claims about interchangeability of different religions became reframed by the comparative disciplines so important to Howitt s project. Howitt had no immediate access to the intellectual world of Fox and Blount. Rather, his foray into comparative anticlericalism propelled him into the academic and political problematics of the British Empire.
In 1833, when Quaker leaders gathered in London for the Yearly Meeting of the Society of Friends, they reviewed a prospectus of Howitt s History of Priestcraft and decided to denounce as a libelous work that Friends would be cautioned not to read. To the mind of Mary Howitt, William s wife, this was just as well. Their disapproval would in reality do the book good, the very caution inflaming curiosity and attracting attention to it. [71] Mary thought that George Fox and William Penn would have liked her husband s book very much. If modern Quakers did not, the fault did not lie with William. Friends, she wrote in a letter of June 1833, have adopted a more timid policy in these days, and are more inclined to concede to the powers that be than stand boldly opposed to them. [72]
In this matter, the two Howitts were of a single mind. Like Mary, William thought that the Society of Friends had deteriorated since its inception, and he made
his opinion known in an 1833 article on George Fox and his Contemporaries. In Howitt s estimation, when the 1689 Act of Toleration (1689) stopped the persecution of Quakers, it also triggered the Society s long decline by causing the effervescence of the early movement to settle into a dull literalism. Wealth and rank overtook the Friends, and their radical roots withered. Howitt hoped that his contemporaries would recoup the original spirit of the movement by instituting key reforms, including the abandonment of Quaker peculiarities of speech and dress (stubborn insistence on the informal thou had come to serve a very different function after the pronoun was dropped from everyday English). Although his article was not well received among Society elders, younger members did appreciate his sentiments. This reflected support among English Quakers for American Elias Hicks (1748-1830) rejection of Quaker orthodoxy, which had resulted in the great schism of American Friends in 1828.[73]
Above all, then, Howitt was concerned with managing the minority status of
Quakers. This is not surprising, given the legal reforms of the late 1820s. In 1828, the Test and Corporation Acts, which had placed legal disabilities on religious minorities since the 1660s and 70s, were repealed. This was followed in 1829 by the
emancipation of Catholics. As Gauri Viswanathan has suggested, the shift signaled by these reforms was more complicated than a simple extension of the legal structures of tolerance or the removal of disabilities. Closely related to simultaneously developments in India, the new legislation was meant to incorporate minorities into the national body by assimilating them to the dominant values of a national culture newly remobilized expressly for this purpose. As Viswanathan points out, Tory support of the bill was motivated in part by the conviction that aiming for a nation of good Englishmen was a more realistic goal than achieving a nation of good Anglicans. For the new minorities, their difference from the national norm was both effaced and retained: they were remade as non-Jewish Jews, non-Catholic Catholics, non-dissenting Dissenters, nonnoncomforming Nonconformists, and so forth. [74] English liberalism thus rose to prominence by producing new contradictions within the concept of the citizen. As non-dissenting Dissenters the Quakers would indeed have ceded their some portion of their minority power status, as well as the critical purchase on state power that minority status often entails. With The Popular History of Priestcraft, Howitt tried to render this destabilizing conjuncture a moment of maneuver for his religious minority. Howitt wanted to recoup Quakers minority status, which in his view had been compromised since 1689. He proposed two means for doing so. First, he would reinstate the oppositional ethos of Quaker origins. Second, he would look beyond England to court transnational solidarities, by lumping Quakers together with other anticlerical agitators in all ages and nations. Thus positioned at the margins of the English nation, Quakers could proudly identify as members of a fully global minority: the fearless critics of sacerdotal religion.
Newly revivified, the Quakers could then further expand the moment of maneuver produced by post-1828 volatility in their minority status. It would seem that, in the late seventeenth century, when the problem of religious dissent was provisionally resolved with creation of the protected category of the religious minority, the content of dissent was neutralized as protected minority belief. With the legal structure of religious minority-dom up for question, Howitt seemed to think that the time was ripe once again to advocate seriously for the full disestablishment of the Church of England. The History of Priestcraft is, above all else, a screed against the state s official support of Anglicanism. Howitt quotes George Fox to bolster his claim that if a government patronizes one religion, it punishes all others, whether the Catholic majority in Ireland or the Quaker, Dissenting, and Catholic minorities in England. The established church, he goes on to claim, is even bad for the Anglicans. It strangles Oxford and Cambridge with sinecures. It burdens parishes with privately appointed pastors, often the sluggard nephews of the rich.
When the History of Priestcraft was published, it catapulted Howitt to new prominence as one of Nottingham s most celebrated Radicals. His new connections allow him to take his complains to the government. In January 1834, he and a few other delegates were sent to Prime Minister Earl Grey (r. 1830-1834) to petition for the full disestablishment of the Church of England. The Earl, however, did not take their request seriously. As Mary Howitt wrote that month:
His Lordship, after reading the petition, told the deputation that he was sorry to find the expression of such sweeping measures, which would embarrass the Ministers, alarm both Houses of Parliament, and startle the country. He wished they had confined themselves to the removal of those disabilities connected with marriage, burial, registration, and such matters, for on these heads there existed, both in himself and his colleagues, every disposition to relieve them . Did they want entirely to do away with all establishment of religion?
William Howitt replied in no uncertain terms that that was precisely what they desired. The Earl, displeased with this response, vowed to oppose Howitt s efforts.[75] Disestablishment was not to be.
The History of Priestcraft may not have the impact on national politics that its author had hoped for. But, as I suggested above, the nation was not its ultimate horizon. Howitt s History reread English religion through a global frame of reference, making its case for disestablishment by harnessing a world history of religious imposture. A single moral lesson, Howitt writes, is stamped on the destinies of every nation. In order to enjoy happiness, mutual love, and general prosperity, the people must snatch from the hands of their spiritual teachers all political power, and confine them solely to their legitimate task of Christian instruction (PHP, 247). The true Dissenting spirit will not rest until all humanity has been delivered from sacerdotal authority. From age to age, the great spirits of the world have raised their voices and cried Liberty! (250). Howitt clearly counts himself among these great spirits, asserting his solidarity with a global Non-conformism that protests the near-universal power of crafty priests. This transnational solidarity serves to reinforce Quaker minority status within the English nation, cementing and fracturing Howitt s attempted return to the stridently anticlerical spirit of George Fox.
If George Fox had provided Howitt with the conceptual apparatus that he used to impugn the justice of a state-sponsored church, he did not offer adequate conceptual resources for writing a global history of clerical oppression. For this, Howitt had to turn to a different intellectual lineage, to a set of thinkers that allowed him to postulate heathen conformities, or the comparability and substitutability of religions. It is to that other set of thinkers that I now turn.
In one particularly enigmatic passage in the Popular History of Priestcraft, Howitt describes a cadre of Aztec priests who, arrayed before the credulous mass, call out to their deity in order to distract the multitude from their own dubious claim to divine authority. They cry out, if not exactly Great is Diana of the Ephesians, great is Mexitli of the Azticas (PHP, 48).[76] Thus does Charles Blount s Great is Diana of the Ephesians
(1680) enter into Howitt s Popular History.
Charles Blount, gentleman and man of letters, may not number among the most celebrated freethinkers of the English Enlightenment. Nevertheless, he remains notable for his popular adaptation of work by other, more influential authors like Thomas
Hobbes (1588-1679), Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677), and Edward, Lord Herbert of Cherbury (1583-1648). By citing Blount, however obliquely, William Howitt invoked the history of what historian Frank Manuel has termed the imposture theory of religion: the notion that religion per se amounts to nothing but fraud. [77][78] As this dissertation is centrally concerned with the imposture theory and its multiple genealogies, I will take this
opportunity to track the history to which Howitt alludes (the standard history of Enlightenment theories of priestly fraud). As historians like Frank Manuel, Peter Harrison, and Justin Champion have suggested, the closing decades of the seventeenth century were a pivotal moment for the consolidation of the imposture theory, and it is thus notable that this is the moment Howitt turns to in writing his History of Priestcraft.
Charles Blount stepped into prominence in 1678, the year that he joined the Green Ribbon Club (a prominent organ of Whig dismay over Charles II and his alleged papist proclivities) and published his Anima Mundi, or, an historical narration of the opinions of the ancients concerning man s soul after this life (which subtitle notwithstanding had very modern implications, arousing the ire of a bishop and even inspiring book burnings). The next year, Blount published An Appeal from the Country to the City (1679), which spun conspiratorial tales of the Popish Plot to take over London. Great is Diana of the Ephesians (1680), his most thorough exposition of the imposture theory of religion, quickly followed. Before his lovelorn suicide in 1693, Blount published two other major denunciations of religious supernaturalism (Miracles, No Violations of the Laws of Nature
[1683], Oracles of Reason [1693]). [79]
Blount s irreverent skepticism places him squarely within the world of the radical Enlightenment. [80] In many ways, his work anticipated the far more scandalous allegations of imposture made by the anonymous Trait des trois imposteurs (c.1719), perhaps the quintessential text of the eighteenth century s clandestine radical scene.[81] The Trait held to a hard materialism, dismissing all supernatural claims as but human fictions and pure illusions given birth by the politics of Princes and of Priests. [82] Blount, however, stopped short of radical materialism, instead using the imposture narrative to bolster belief in a rationalist religion. Like Herbert of Cherbury, of whom he was the only self-acknowledged disciple, Blount was a Deist, and he claimed that understanding imposture was the key to reviving natural religion.[83]
Blount demonstrates his commitment to Deist monotheism in his major histories of religious fraud. In Anima Mundi, Blount posited an Original of superstition, a first fraud, that did certainly proceed from some crafty discerning person out to procure an esteem and credit in the World. [84] Later, in Great is Diana, he elaborated this tale of primal deceit, explaining that in the beginning humanity held to a natural monotheism presided over by virtuous philosophers. The Edenic state came to an end, however, when the people were seduced by their crafty and covetous Sacerdotal Order; who instead of the said Virtue and Piety, introduced Fable and Fictions of their own coining. These charlatans convinced the multitude that,
henceforth, God would only communicate via priests. They devised a vast catalogue of crimes in order to further the trade in divine forgiveness; proliferated divinities to produce a lucrative polytheism; faked theatrical miracles; and introduced the custom of sacrifice, the greatest and most mysterious fourbs that ever were invented, to confirm their rule by fear.18 Meanwhile, they marginalized the philosophers to prevent them from detecting and decrying their impostures.
Blount borrowed the basic form of this narrative from Herbert of Cherbury.
Herbert had, in his De Veritate (1624), sought to uncover through a priori reflection a set Common Notions underlying all religions.19 But, after deciding on them, Herbert hit upon a snag: the growing literature on pagan religion, classical and contemporary, proved his Notions to be anything but common. So he added an addendum to his theory: the common religion, with its Common Notions, had long ago been corrupted by a Sacerdotal Order that pioneered the great Defection from the Pure Worship of the Supreme God. 20 The reasoning Deist might restore the natural order by recovering the pure monotheism lost to the priests.
For Herbert, the primal fraud was a footnote to eternal monotheism; but for
Blount, monotheism becomes but a minor episode in the epic tale of fraud s unfolding.
18 Charles Blount, Great is Diana of the Ephesians, or the Original of Idolatry ( 3-15.
19 Edward Lord Herbert of Cherbury, De veritate, prout distinguitur a revelatione, a verisimili, a possibili, et a falso, trans. Meyrick H. Carr (Bristol: J. W. Arrowsmith, 1937). Herbert settled on five Common Notions:
(1) that there is a supreme God, (2) that God is to be worshipped, (3) that virtue and piety are at the heart of religion, (4) that we must repent our wickedness, and (5) that after this life we await reward and punishment. Herbert is often hailed as a precursor of the comparative study of religion that emerged in the nineteenth century. See Morris Jastrow, The Study of Religion (London: Charles Scribner, 1901), 133136; Eric Sharpe, Comparative Religion: A History, 2nd ed. (LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1986 [1975]), 16; and J.
Samuel Preus, Explaining Religion: Criticism and Theory from Bodin to Freud (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1987), 23-39; and Peter Byrne, Natural Religion and the Nature of Religion: The Legacy of Deism (New York: Routledge, 1989).
20 Edward Lord Herbert of Cherbury, The antient religion of the gentiles, and causes of their errors consider d (London: William Taylor, 1711), 3, 41.
Taken tendentiously, Blount s Diana writes the Notions out of Herbert s De Veritate. The common cause of religion, at least as we know it, is fraud, pure and simple. Blount s program, to be sure, remains Deist in orientation. As he clarified in a 1693 essay, it is their faith in external things or bare opinions of the mind that puts the followers of the Particular religions at risk for the cheat of the religious imposture. Deism peers behind externals to find its deity; because it worships God negatively, it remains immune to human lies.[85] But Blount introduced an instability into this paradigm. When Herbert had peered behind religious particulars, he found find the serene effulgence of divine reason; when Blount peered behind the curtain of religious particulars, he kept sticking on huckster priests. The stagecraft of conniving charlatans might conceal yet a deeper recess, the true temple of the divine, but this final step could just as easily be dispensed with. Radical materialism is only a step away.
But, as Peter Harrison has noted, Blount and other proponents of critical deism, alongside their clear affinities with radical thought, also shared in an anticlerical sentiment that was widespread in early modern England.[86] During the late seventeenth century, a richly varied body of satirical writing lambasted the clergy for a variety of ends. John Eachard s The Grounds and Occasions of the Contempt of the Clergy and Religion (1670), for instance, diagnosed the poor policies that had rendered English clerics pompous, bumbling, and generally laughable, bringing disesteem not only on themselves, but also on God.[87] At the same time, clerics were also satirized on stage such that, in the words of one outraged observer, glorious Religion was made the Diversion of the Town, and the Scorn of Buffoons. [88] While Blount s anticlerical writings share a strong affinity with radical texts from the Continent, like the Trait des Trois Imposteurs, they also need to be understood as part of this wider English anticlerical culture.
Indeed, as Justin Champion has argued, it is precisely the historiographical tendency to entangle the English and French Enlightenments that has rendered English anticlericalism invisible to theorists of modernity. Champion follows J. G. A. Pocock s claim that English anticlericalism remained more muted than its French counterpart (i.e. Voltaire s crasez l inf me ) because in England there was simply no inf me to be crushed. [89] Consequently, some of the most trenchant critics of the period were, like
Jonathan Swift, also card-carrying clerics. As Champion aptly summarizes the situation, the English Enlightenment was inscribed from within the prophetic. [90] Secular and sacred criticisms were not clearly demarcated and, for this reason, it makes more sense to conceive of the two together as composing an anticlerical modernity (I discuss this proposal at greater length in the Introduction). The intertwined history of these two anticlericalisms is clearly evident in Howitt s Popular History of Priestcraft, with its double invocation of Blount and Fox.
A parallel argument might be made with regard to the French Enlightenment, which, to paraphrase Champion, seems to have been inscribed from within the demonic or, at least, the demonological. Take, for instance, the Histoire des oracles (1686) by Bernard le Boivier de Fontenelle (1657-1757). [91] This treatise on the trickery of ancient oracles adapted Antonius Van Dale s ponderous Latin treatise De Oraculis (1683) for popular audiences; not long after its publication, it was translated into English by Blount s friend Aphra Behn (1640-1689) (she is best known today for authoring the Oriental tale Oroonoko [1688]). The text remained a touchstone for eighteenth century debates about pagan religion and religious imposture.[92] The Histoire refuted the accepted dogma that the coming of Christ had silenced pagan oracles because they were inspired by demons. Fontenelle revised sacred history by placing priests at the helm of fake religion. The oracles were silenced, not because perfidious devils were hushed by Christ, but because shifting political structures upended all-too-human theatrics. Fontenelle played an important role in disenchanting the ancient
Mediterranean world for modern audiences, replacing real (that is, supernatural) magic with its secular (that is, theatrical) double.[93]
Although the disjuncture between these two narratives, between demons and charlatans, is unmistakably important, the continuity between them should not be ignored. If Fontenelle was able to displace the demons, he retained the structure of suspicion that belief in demons had promulgated: demonic deceit prepared the way for priestly deceit. A version of this argument has been made by Michel de Certeau in his study of the mass demonic possession of Ursuline nuns at the convent of Loudun in the 1630s and 1640s. By analyzing the shifting discursive formations that constellated around the possessed women, Certeau demonstrates how exorcism, as a struggling against the lie of the demon, became an important site for the articulation of new regimes of truth, new modes of state power and public spectacle, and new medicalizations of the body.[94] The demonic specter thus comes to haunt even the most paradigmatic of modern epistemologies, including the radical skepticism of Ren
Descartes (1596-1650), who was dogged by a doubter s devil with alleged links to Loudun.[95] Disappearing demons also influenced events beyond France. They possessed colonized subjects in Spain s new world empire. [96] They also influenced English Deist accounts of the fall from primal monotheism. Previously, Satan had been the paradigmatic Artificer of fraud and Eve our credulous mother the prototypical dupe; the secularized Enlightenment iteration of this narrative replaced the Devil with the perfidious priest and Eve with the credulous mass.[97] The basic plotline, however, remained the same.
While treatises like Fontenelle s and Blount s were important to the development of the imposture theory, they were always situated with networks of popular practice centered on spectacular entertainments and material culture. As scholars like Leigh Eric Schmidt and Simon During have so deftly demonstrated, the imposture theory emerged through intersections of philosophy and entertainment, scientific experiment and magical display, print and performance. [98] Philosopherventriloquists, mock oracles, and talking pigs were pioneers in the field of enlightened entertainment ; they rendered the magician one of the alluring celebrities of the Enlightenment, a wizard arrayed against wizardry, an exposer of supernatural humbugs. [99] Such entertainments used illusion to train their audiences in skepticism, redisciplining the senses with new technologies like the acoustic tube.[100] Writers like
Fontenelle and Blount indulged in this theatrical sensibility, delving into the acoustic effects of mountains and caverns, detailing priests fantastical Vestments and stately Representations, and reinforcing the truth claims of print with metaphors of ocular clarity. As Blount put it, priests perfidious craft was a was a kind of Acting their Religion, as it were, upon a Stage. [101] I would note that Blount s claim here echoes the theory of the religious perverformative laid out in the introduction. Priestcraft haunts true religion because it recalls the perpetual possibility that the sacred might misfire, performing not religion but instead the perversely irreligious parodies of the stage.
If enlightened entertainments sometimes seemed to reinforce the class-based division between the rational few and the credulous many, further subordinating the mass to their instructors, this was no mistake. The imposture theory implied a distinctly antagonistic class politics, particularly when in the form of the twofold philosophy. [102] Critical Deists and others, adapting a popular classical tradition, posited a sharp divide between the philosopher and the mass (a divide important, for instance, to Blount s origin narrative). As John Toland once wrote: We shall be in Safety if we separate ourselves from the Multitude; for the Multitude is a proof of what is worst. [103] The intellectual elite resolved to keep their pearls of wisdom from the swine of the credulous, superstitious mob [104]; they thus transformed the truths of natural religion
into a mystery that was veiled from the people and hinted at only in hieroglyphic code.[105] Intellectual radicalism, though it may have inspired a benevolent elitism, did not do much to undermine prevailing social hierarchies a feature that would make the imposture theory especially appealing to imperial ideologues in India.
The theory would not have made it to India, however, had it not been for one final feature. Deists like Blount gathered together the various intellectual lineaments outlined above, and their anticlerical spirit fully of a piece with its period. But they transformed this common anticlericalism into something novel, into what Peter Harrison deems a full-blown theory of religion. Deists criticized the English clergy by presenting them as contemporary manifestations of a universal religious type the priestly imposter. [106] This universal imposter followed on the heels of Herbert s Common Notions, extrapolating his universality from the presumed universality of minimum religion, which was Herbert s fundamental innovation. Universal fraud became the foil to universal faith, and the tension between the two furthered the fashioning of a new discursive entity, a religion greater than the sum of its parts. The mythos of priestly deceit had a clear effect on the major naturalist theories of religion that emerged during the eighteenth century. David Hume s Natural History of Religion (1757), for instance, faults fraudulent priests for the loss of the rational monotheism that prevailed in the first ages of the world. What I hope to have called attention to in the above discussion, however, is the critical contiguity of naturalism and supernaturalism, of Christianity and its critics. I have used the revisionist position elaborated by Justin Champion, Mark Goldie, and others to insist on the importance of Christian anticlericalism in the making of secular modernity. Christian anticlericalism did not give way with the rise of its materialist cousin; it thrived. And as it continued to mutate, the two anticlericalisms came to inform each other. The religious and the secular thus come to share a single critical position, their differences in belief receding behind their common skeptical apparatus.
William Howitt s ability to arrogate the more radical breed of anticlericalism to the Quaker reformism of the 1830s (close kin to Evangelical movements of the same period) further reinforces the revisionist claim. A slogan like Great is Diana of the Ephesians is just as useful to the Protestant polemicist as to the atheist, and it retained its potency well beyond the 1680s. Indeed, Howitt s History of Priestcraft further textures Mark Goldie s suggestion that the conceptual apparatus of priestly imposture began to take on new forms around 1844, with the publication of Karl Marx s Contribution on the Critique of Hegel s Philosophy of Right (see Introduction). A decade earlier, in 1833, another effort to rethink religious deceit had been undertaken. Howitt s history of universal priestcraft may not have proved as influential as Marx s incipient theory of ideology, but both texts sought to resuscitate and revise related narrative tropes of divine hokum and exposure. As Howitt s History demonstrates, in the early decades of the nineteenth century, the twin legacies of Charles Blount and George Fox had taken on a renewed salience.
For all the ways that the History of Priestcraft is a critical and skeptical text, intent on tearing down institutional establishments in the name of Christian protest, it is also heavily invested in what was in the 1830s an increasingly institutionalized array of disciplinary procedures. Howitt was a critic set on establishing what I will call (borrowing a phrase from Frank Manuel) heathen conformities. This phrase has an insidiously authoritarian ring to it for a reason. The imperial West articulated its difference from the rest of the world through knowledge regimes that generated stereotypes about the colonized and then, through a range of coercive mechanisms, induced the colonized to conform to those stereotypes; in the process, and even while proliferating massively documented differences, these knowledge regimes also established the fundamental equivalence or interchangeability of colonial subjects. The heathens, in their infinite variety, are by definition not to be confused with Christians, but rather with each other.
Howitt was working in this general mode when he set out to shew that priestcraft in all ages and all nations has been the same; that its nature is one, and that nature essentially evil. That is, he gathered together a very wide array of cultural data from around the world and forced all the collocated customs, practices, and anecdotes to conform to a single pattern, a hypothesis proven before it was even tested. All the world s heathens conform to the pattern of priestcraft. In fact, their subservience to priests is what, at bottom, defines them as heathens and separates them from true Christians (Howitt was not particularly shy about classing Catholics and Anglicans with the superstitious mobs of the colonized world).
In his search for heathen conformities, Howitt engaged in a task prevalent since at least the time of Blount and his contemporaries. In the early modern period, the learned devoured new information about two types of pagans : one featured in translations from classical Greek and Latin, the other in travelers accounts of the nonWestern world. This public, in its effort to make sense of its newly widened reality, eagerly drew parallels between these two disparate domains. According to Frank Manuel, by the early eighteenth century the repeated juxtaposition of the two paganisms, classical and contemporary, had fundamentally transformed perceptions of both. By 1724, when Jesuit missionary Joseph Fran ois Lafitau published his Moeurs des sauvages am riquains compar es aux moeurs des premiers temps, the two had, he suggests, been completely assimilated with each other. [107] Or, as S.N. Balagangadhara has put it, paganism was a hybrid beast that lived among the peoples and cultures of Asia but
came to the witness stand clothed in the sacerdotal robes of the Ancients. [108][109]
The mutual assimilation of ancient and modern paganisms proved a boon to the emergent human sciences in their effort to impose systematic order on a new world of things. But it also raised new satirical possibilities for the religious critic. Could the cry of Diana be placed on the lips of a Catholic or even an Anglican priest? For many, the answer was an emphatic yes. Chains of priestly equivalence structured many, if not most, Enlightenment treatises on religious imposture, and it was often only because of the clever substitution of clerics that criticisms of Christianity could be published
without seriously endangering their authors. Some, however, thought that to grant the comparability of Christianity and heathenism was to concede far too much. As
Anthony Collier wrote in his 1698 denunciation of theatrical satire: Can we argue from Heathenism to Christianity? How can the practise be the same, where the Rule is so very different? Is there no Distinction between Truth and Fiction, between Majesty and a Pageant? Must God be treated like an Idol? [110] The more that the object Christianity entered into referential relation with equivalent objects under the banner of the newly reconstituted signifier religion, the less it could presume to the status of religion s ultimate referent and ground. Consequently, the new ordering of religions posed real a danger to the claims of orthodoxy.
In many ways, Howitt s nineteenth century entry into this field of knowledge is strikingly continuous with its late seventeenth century predecessors. It is the presumption of heathen conformity that permits his glib substitution of the slogan Great is Mexitli of the Aziticas [sic] for Great is Diana of the Ephesians. He seems, moreover, to have strategically displaced his harshest critiques of Anglican clerics onto their heathen analogues. As his wife Mary wrote, while he shows the tyrannical spirit of priestcraft in all ages and nations, he will treat moderately, comparatively speaking, the subject of priesthood in the present day; that is, he will war with the principle, and not with the men. [111] Howitt s critics also seemed to replay a much older set of debates. For instance, the introduction to the American edition of the History of Priestcraft reframes Collier s complaint. Written by a clergyman of New York, the introduction faults Howitt for unwarranted apposition and insufficient discrimination between divine decree and human corruption. Howitt erred in classifying the true religion (i.e. Protestant Christianity) with the inventions of the dragon. While Howitt s Quakerism might account for his indiscriminately anti-clerical proclivities, it does not entirely excuse it. One should never confuse, as Howitt apparently did, John the Apostle with Demetrius the shrine-maker of Diana (PHP, viii-x).
Despite these apparent continuities, however, Howitt s History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations is different in kind from similar ventures of the 1680s and 90s. In the intervening century, an array of new disciplinary formations had emerged that refashioned the conceptual tools available for comparative anticlericalism. The nascent human sciences had intensified, systematized, and institutionalized the search for heathen conformities in an era when the West s political interest in those same heathens was very much on the rise. The grand apparatus of Orientalism, although not to receive its full elaboration until later, had begun to emerge by 1830, and Howitt s
History of Priestcraft is disciplined by its novel array of classificatory technologies. Briefly, Howitt structured his History around a narrative of common human descent from the sons of the biblical patriarch Noah. This diffusionist narrative was a common one in late eighteenth and early nineteenth century efforts to map world history. It combined modified Christian dogma with an early form of scientific race theory, reinforcing the claims of both with copious philological detail. William Jones (1746-1794) was perhaps the most important advocate of the diffusionist paradigm, as in his influential essay On the Gods of Greece, Italy, and India (1784); and Howitt includes Jones in his appreciative list of acute and industrious antiquarians whose research enabled his own study of how every pagan worship in the world has the same origin (PHP, 17, 21). Howitt s History was not a neutral presentation of this body of research, however; it clearly took sides in a scholarly debate that had been raging for decades. According to Nigel Leask, eighteenth-century mythography was split over the question of Christian belief. Two camps had laid claim to the discipline: radical mythographers intent on reducing all myth, Christian included, to natural allegory; and conservative mythographers who tried to trace all world mythologies back to the Biblical Flood.[112] Howitt recycles material from both sides of this debate, but his preference is clearly for the authors in the latter camp. He cites Jacob Bryant (17151804), who argued that all heathen mythologies were corruptions of an antediluvian monotheism. Bryant paid particular attention to how Noah s son Ham and his progeny the Cushites spread this corruption.[113] Howitt also cited Thomas Maurice (1754-1824) and his follower G.S. Faber (1773-1854). Both were Anglican clergymen who updated Bryant s theories in light of William Jones pioneering research. Maurice s major obsession was the Trinity; he sought to catalogue divine threesomes around the world so as to argue for the phylogenetic priority of Christian Trinitarianism.[114]
Howitt, ever eclectic in his intellectual sensibility, incorporated material from these and others texts. His laundry list of heathen conformities includes trinities, solar worship, human sacrifice, phallic rites, auguries, metempsychosis, self-immolation, arks, and mysterious caves. But the most prominent and defining principle of global paganism is, of course, the despotic rule of priests. Priestcraft, the ultimate heathen conformity, implies a system of domination in the few, and slavery in the multitude
(PHP, 42). It began in an early age of the world, after the Flood and before Babel, when the whole human family was together in one place. Pure patriarchal worship was corrupted by priestly deceit, and from this lie arose every system of heathen mythology. The pollution worked its way across the globe with Noah s sons: Japhet populated Europe, Siberia, and the Americas; Shem populated Asia; and Ham populated Africa (16-18). By the onset of modernity, priestcraft prevailed worldwide: From the temple of Buddh and Jaggernath in India, to the stony circles of Druidism in Europe; from the snowy wastes of Siberia and Scandinavia to the north, to the most southern lands of Africa and America, the fires of these bloody deities rejoiced the demoniac priests and consumed the people (24).
India, however, looms largest, and for an important reason. Since at least the 1790s, extremely vocal Evangelical and Reformist elements in England had advocated for the civilizing mission of empire. The moral debacle of British economic expansion into India, showcased in the trial of Warren Hastings (1788-1795), had prompted a sustained outcry from those who thought that Christianity could right the moral
wrongs of empire. Evangelical leaders like William Wilberforce (1759-1833) mounted a
Bulmer, 1812); the text claims that the wily Brahmins and the French atheists have formed an unholy alliance in order to subordinate Christ to Krishna.
campaign to use the 1813 renewal of the East India Company s charter to throw the subcontinent open to missionaries. In the process, these reformists developed a rhetoric about the moral turpitude of Hindoo India, blaming the sorry state of subcontinental ethics on the greed of crafty brahmin priests. This polemical discourse was predicated on the long-standing assumption of the comparability of
heathenisms, as is evinced by the centrality of priestcraft to both traditions. Reformist rhetors and polemicists knew considerably less about the religious particulars of India than they did about the universal type of the conniving charlatan priest.
Howitt s History of Priestcraft, published twenty years after the Charter Act of 1813, devotes an entire chapter to this tired trope. Aside from England, India is the only nation in this global narrative to warrant a full chapter, and this is because of the unique place that India holds in the history of priestcraft. As Howitt explains: of all the semi-barbarous nations beset by priests, India is the worst. The brahmans have established their unparalleled priestly despotism by fabricating and sanctifying an unusually complete system of social division. Their soul-quelling caste system leaves
millions on millions bound, from the earliest ages to the present hour in chains.
The people are rendered slavish in the servility of a religious creed that is so subtilly framed that the moral regeneration of the swarming myriads of these vast regions seems almost entirely hopeless (PHP, 74-75). In the dreamtime of religious origins, we final not the primal pur$%a but the primal deceit: an outrageous fabrication of var!as inserted into the mouth of Manu. The clever brahmins firmly seized and secured the whole political power. Restricting access to knowledge and manipulating the masses with promises of future happiness, they lulled India into a millenniumlong stupor. From such a labyrinth of priestly art, nothing short of a miracle seems capable of rescuing them (87).
Once turned toward this den priestly iniquity, Howitt seems to have been drawn ineluctably deeper into the problem of colonialism. Swept up into national and international radical politics, William and Mary began to protest slavery and other excesses of imperialism without, however, calling for the outright abolition of empire. Instances of their activities during this period include a series of events from 1840: in an Eclectic Review article on The Present Condition of British India, William advocated securing cotton revenues for Indians; William was elected to the general committee of the British India Society; and Mary attended the World Anti-Slavery Convention in
London (where she and the other female delegates, including Lucretia Mott and
Elizabeth Cady Stanton were infamously relegated to the balcony).
William Howitt s sentiments about the British Empire are laid forth in his 1838 opus his Colonization and Christianity. The book aimed to lay open to the public the most extensive and extraordinary system of crime which the world ever witnessed. It is a system which has been in full operation for more than three hundred years and continues yet in unabating activity of evil. [115] (In this, colonialism surely bears comparison to priestcraft). As in the earlier book, India (the Ireland of the East ) occupies pride of place, taking up seven out of twenty-eight chapters. Although Howitt is very critical of British imperial policies, he does not advocate for the relinquishment of the empire. Rather, he wants for Christianity to serve as the British Empire s moral compass. There is no power but the spirit of Christianity living in the heart of the British public, which can secure justice to the millions that are crying for it from every region of the earth. It is that which must stand as the perpetual watch and guardian of humanity; and never yet has it failed. [116] This passage clarifies how Howitt s concern with colonialism followed from his concern with priestcraft: it was precisely because of India s clerical excesses that it had to be colonized. This was to be an ethical empire with a civilizing mission of cultural reform. Howitt s Quaker passion for social justice propelled him, however ironically, to support the colonial domination of India. In an 1842 essay, William suggested that the British India Society s humanitarian intervention might save for Britain the finest possessions which ever were put under the control of another nation. [117] After the early 1840s, the Howitt s drifted from their Reformist zeal. As Sven Lindqvist has pointed out, in their later translations of Scandinavian literature, the Howitts attributed Britain s imperial successes to its Viking heritage a conquering blood of which they were proud.[118]
What I want to
emphasize, however, is how anticlerical raillery of the 1830s took the Empire,
and India in particular, as its inevitable horizon. Howitt had crafted his
anticlericalism from the double lineage of George Fox and Charles Blount,
hoping to challenge the Quaker establishment, the Church of England, and the
new liberal mode of citizenship emerging in the newly tolerant British state.
If ideas are bricks to be thrown through the windows of power, the idea of
religious imposture found itself in the early nineteenth century suspended
between the gravitational pull of two political edifices, one ecclesiastical
and the other imperial. This chapter has focused on the first of those poles;
the next will focus on the second.
The Brahmin stood in the place of the Deity to the infatuated sons of Indian superstition; the will of heaven was thought to issue from his lips; and his decision was reverenced as the fiat of destiny the name of God, by this perversion, was made use of to sanction and support the most dreadful species of despotism; a despotism, which, not content with subjugating the body, tyrannized over the prostrate faculties of the enslaved mind.
Thomas Maurice (1801) [119]
Baptist missionary William Ward (1769-1823) once proclaimed the Hindoo religion the greatest piece of priestcraft and the most formidable system of idolatry that has ever existed in the world. Under its auspices, a sixth part of the Human Race are mocked and deluded, for the benefit of crafty men. [120] With anticlerical flair, Ward uses the imposture theory of religion to establish Hindu belief as an object of study, fitting Hinduism into a ready-made narrative of religious delusion so as to cement his own Protestant claim to religious preeminence. And, as this chapter will demonstrate, he was not alone in doing so.
Throughout the colonial period, deceit, credulity, and illusion remained the conceptual linchpins for representations of Hinduism and of Indian religions more broadly. Many commentators would surely have agreed with the comments published by one Mr. Farrar in December 1832 (the very month that William Howitt was completing his History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations): Brahmins have seized on every thing that is agreeable or wonderful, and made it subservient to their priestcraft.
The rivers, the springs, the mountains, the plains, the trees, the stones, all that is animate, and all that is inanimate, are fashioned and moulded into their system, and made to uphold their hydra-headed superstition. [121] Mr. Farrar was by no means the only British writer to claim that hydra-headed Brahmanism dominated the Indian subcontinent. In the early decades of the nineteenth century, Hinduism was equated with priestcraft at least as often as India was equated with Hinduism. Even Orientalists smitten with Sanskrit literature were drawn to the concept: William Jones, for instance, abhor[ed] the sordid priestcraft of Durga s ministers, while insisting that their fraud no more affects the sound religion of the Hindus, than the lady of Loretto and the Romish impositions affect our own rational faith. [122] Indian Muslims, although,
tyrannized by their Moulahs, Imans, and Moonshees, were usually thought not
quite so much tyrannized as the Hindus.[123]
This chapter will interrogate the dominant paradigm of missionary discourse that, according to historian Geoffrey Oddie, emerged between 1792 and 1840. Its major proponents were Charles Grant (1746-1823), William Carey (1761-1834), William Ward (1769-1823), Claudius Buchanan (1766-1815), Bishop Reginald Heber (1783-1826), and, a little later, Alexander Duff (1806-1878). These missionary writers were extremely important to the colonial reconsolidation of Hinduism. They helped naturalize the idea that India s overlapping devotional cultures formed a single, subcontinental system devised and managed by a priestly elite. This brahmanical pan-Indian model of Hinduism relied on several assumptions, mostly notably the presumed preeminence of Sanskrit texts and their brahman interpreters. In addition to cuing Orientalism s keen nostalgia for the classical past, this assumption also enabled the idea that brahmans had engineered the entire Hindu system for their material benefit.6 It was this Hinduism that would come to seem comparable to Christianity. Founded on fraud, it was easy to dismiss this polemic reduction as Christianity s counterfeit. [124] To be sure, missionaries agendas differed from those of the Company-state both before and after 1813; but, as I will argue below, their activities were central to the broader field of imperial power in the early decades of the nineteenth century.[125]
6 Oddie, Imagined Hinduism, 95.
I approach what Duff called the spiritual invasion of India by way of the crafty priest.[126] While the previous chapter attempted a history of the imposture theory of religion, here I attend more to its conceptual grammar, as it was articulated in the mission field of India. The chapter calls attention to three primary dimensions of the discourse of priestcraft in colonial India. First, I consider how it intersected with the discourse of Oriental despotism. Drawing on the work of Nicholas Dirks, I suggest that in the early part of the nineteenth the Company-state shifted its mode of governmentality. It sought to harness the diffuse circuitry of power that suffused
Indian society so as to engineer a newly penetrative ethnographic state. I elaborate
Dirks theory by tracking how imperial ideologues conceived the relation between Oriental despots and Hindoo priests. I argue that the British used both despot and priest as foils for its emergent pastoral style of rule (a term I borrow from Michael Foucault). Missionaries and others in this diffuse field of power sought to reform the souls of the colonized, remaking them as self-governing liberal subjects.
Second, I argue that print media were central to this project. Drawing on Michael Warner s interrogation of what he calls the Whig-McLuhanite paradigm of print media effects, I track the peculiar belief that print artifacts possessed an unstoppable power to undermine traditional religious hierarchies. Missionary writers thought that the printing press would trigger a Protestant Reformation in India, upending Catholic Hinduism just as the Luther-Gutenberg nexus had upended the German clerisy. I suggest that missionaries like Alexander Duff and William Ward used
print media to re-discipline the unruly multitudes convened by Hindu devotional practices, reconstituting them as critical publics silent, reflective, and (most importantly) immaterial. Finally, I point to the means by which the narrative of print media s transformative abilities unraveled. These include the raucous arena of print distribution: in its networks of physical exchange, print artifacts did sometimes convene unpredictable embodied publics. They also include the stylistic rifts produced by the literary-textual position that I will term the subaltern skeptic.
Finally, I parse the dimension of the Whig-McLuhanite paradigm most important to the imposture theory of religion and the polemics of priestcraft: the epistemology of exposure. If priestly multitudes were to be remade as self-governing readerly publics, it would be through the public display of Hinduism. Alexander Duff suggested that any public exhibition of Hinduism would expose its falsities and therefore unravel the entire system. In my discussion, I attempt to unpack some of what is encoded in Duff s use of the word exposure. I argue that he invests the printed word with a quasi-magical ability to produce change in the world. In part, he is correct to do so: as J. L. Austin has so artfully demonstrated, words can directly produce changes in the field of social relations; indeed, colonial treatises on Hinduism might serve as a case in point, insofar as they produced fundamental shifts in how Indian religions were conceptualized. However, Duff was wrong to consider his exhibition of Hinduism an exposure. Conditions for exposure were not, in Austin s terms, felicitous. Rather, the term exposure relays the theatrical sensibility of the performative practice of imposture, skepticism, and belief (what Simon During has termed the magical assemblage ) into a medium (print) in which it produces a set of effects considerably more unpredictable than the prescriptive plotline of charlatanic exposure can account for.
During the early nineteenth century, the East India Company s mode of governmentality shifted decisively. As Nicholas Dirks has argued, at the turn of the century the Company-state still concerned itself primarily with Indian princes, a focus reflected by History s preeminence as the most august of disciplines. In the following decades, however, Anthropology emerged as the principal colonial modality of knowledge and rule. The shift in discipline corresponded to a shift in the field of power; the Company-state had begun to redevelop itself as a biopolitical entity, concerned with classifying and managing the colonized population with new technologies of rule. This process culminated with the full emergence of the
ethnographic state after 1857.[127]
The turn to colonial ethnology may have been animated, in part, by a concern with the ethics of empire. As Dirks suggests, the Warren Hastings trial (1788-1795) scandalized the British public with sordid details of unbridled mercantilist greed. For a moment, it seemed as if the public s moral outrage might bring an end to British imperial expansion in India. However, the sense of scandal was quickly displaced.
Where once scandal referred to the exploits of the colonizers, scandal now began to refer to the lives of the colonized. [128] Vocal reformists out to cure Britain of its social ills began to take note of analogous ills in the colonies. India, they proclaimed, had to be reformed. Otherwise, it would continue to groan under the weight of irrational tradition. And so, the ethical problem presented by Empire found a temporary resolution. Imperial power would change its shape. Henceforth, in addition to transforming states and economies, it must also transform the souls of the colonized. A glowing example of how the intensified concern with Indians moral constitution took up many of the themes of the Hastings trial is the increasingly pervasive worry over the greed and mendacity of the Hindoos; when British writers tried to pin merchants deceptiveness on the Shasters and Debtas, they might have done better to look to the economic conditions set by colonial capitalism itself.[129]
As I will argue, the new mode of colonial governmentality established conceptual and rhetorical connections among Oriental despots, despotic Hindoo priests, and benign British pastors. Political philosophers had long used the Oriental despot as the foil for the bourgeois social order emerging in early modern Europe. Adapted from Aristotle, the theory of Oriental despotism was revived by thinkers like the Baron de Montesquieu (1689-1755), Adam Smith (1723-1790), and Edward Gibbon (1737-1794), and would later frame Karl Marx s exposition of the Asiatic Mode of
Production. [130] In this body of writing, Oriental despots were generally associated with agrarianism, tyrannical deputies, and slave labor. They were thought to hoard economic resources in order to construct lavish monuments that signified their authority. In other words, they represented the feudal order that Europe had so proudly left behind. The free market was celebrated as the antidote to despotism: trade would reform the enslaved multitude to render it a democratic public.14 The theory of Oriental despotism was quickly imported by British writers interested in the history of India. Robert Orme (1728-1801), for instance, used it to analyze the late Mughal Empire; the emperor s despotic deputies, he wrote, had multiplied the miseries of the people of Indostan. 15 The theory s validity, however, did not go unchallenged. William Jones, for one, firmly denied its accuracy as a description of Indian statecraft, actual or ideal.16 But despite its critics, the theory of Oriental despotism remained extremely influential in Western writing about Indian
politics.
The theory acquired some distinctive features when applied to India, most notably an increased emphasis on the power of priests. Indian kings were generally thought to hold less power than their ecclesiastical counterparts. The most influential
articulation of this revised theory of Oriental despotism is to be found in James Mill s
theory s lineage, with a focus on Marx s Asiatic Mode of Production, see Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolutist State (London: NLB, 1974), 462-549.
14 See Mia Carter and Barbara Harlow, Oriental Despotisms and Political Economies, Archives of Empire (Durham: Duke University Press, 2003), 89-90.
15 Robert Orme, Historical Fragments of the Mogul Empire (London: F. Windgrave, 1805 [1782]). Quoted in Carter and Harlow, eds, Archives of Empire, 108-109.
16 For William Jones views on Oriental despotism, see Javed Majeed, Ungoverned Imaginings: James Mill s
History of British India and Orientalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 29-30; and S. N. Mukherjee, Sir William Jones: A Study in Eighteenth-Century British Attitudes to India (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968), 40.
(1773-1836) History of British India (1817). Mill affirms the general theory of Oriental despotism by describing how the Asiatic model permits rule only by the will of a single person with unlimited authority. He modifies the paradigm, however, to make sense of the Indian case: the state s tyranny, although otherwise absolute, never extended to religion and its ministers. [131] True power, Mill claims, was vested in the brahmins, who retained actual and symbolic authority over the king. Indeed, they had cleverly delegated the tedious business of rule to their royal subordinates in order to save themselves from needless work and needless danger.[132] The two evils (church and state) had combined to produce a uniquely noxious condition for the people of
India. As Mill summarizes his position: despotism and priestcraft taken together, the Hindus, in mind and body, were the most enslaved portion of the human race. [133] Mill s displacement of despotism, his transfer of absolute authority from princes to priests, illustrates the period s pervasive shift in interests, as analyzed by Dirks. Where once the contest for India had centered on statecraft, increasingly it would center on priestcraft: the British would have to unseat the priests, India s ultimate and enduring despots, if they wanted to claim unchallenged sovereignty over Indian bodies and souls. The object of the new imperialism was thus to produce autonomous subjects, liberated from Hindu priests and prone to favor British rule. As Eric Stokes has argued, both Evangelicalism and the Utilitarianism, the two primary frames for early
nineteenth century imperialism, were movements of individualism. They sought to liberate the individual from the slavery of custom and from the tyranny of the noble and the priest. Their end was to make the individual in every society a free, autonomous agent, leading a life of conscious deliberation and choice. [134] The great theorist of liberal subjectivity was, of course, James Mill s son, John Stuart Mill (18061873). The younger Mill elaborated his father s account of religious slavery and its effects on the human mind. The savage becomes a slave when he learns obedience, the first lesson of political society. The slave becomes a civilized man when he learns to internalize the direct command so that he can exercise self-government without the immediate application of fear by an outside party. This new breed of self-policing subject, neither savage nor slave, is the basis of modern democratic states.[135] The confluence of discourses (liberal democratic theory, the notion of allpervasive brahminical Hinduism) had clear effects for how imperial ideologues conceived India s political future. As Alexander Duff wrote in 1840, political reform would prove futile unless the potent antecedent cause of false religion were addressed first. Religion was the all in all of India s condition, and so to install representative government or free institutions at the very outset is to begin at the wrong end. To regenerate a people steeped in the very slough of bondage, the colonizing power must first act upon the mind.[136]
With the dawn of the reform era, the Company-state thus assumed a pastoral power over its subjects, and Mill s self-governing individual was a vector for this novel mode of power. As Michel Foucault has argued, around the eighteenth century, a new configuration of power began to emerge in which states would come to intervene simultaneously at the level of the population (scrupulously charting the biopolitical contours of the nation) and of the individual (like a cleric, shaping the individual souls and characters of the ruled).[137] The most obvious form in which the Company-state sought to reshape the subjectivities of the colonized was through its educational policy, particularly Thomas Babington Macaulay s 1835 proposal that English literary education be used to produce a class of persons, Indian in blood and colour, but English, in taste, in opinions, in morals, and in intellect. However, if we assume that imperial power was more diffuse (that is, not limited to the state and its policies), a different class of pastoral powerbrokers comes into view, and one more literally pastoral than the state. In colonial India, legions of would-be pastors roamed plains, hills, and valleys in search of prospective Christian sheep. The aims of these missionaries were certainly never reducible to the aims of the Company; but just as certainly their efforts were central to the diffusion of imperial power, particularly in the first half of the nineteenth century. As British imperialism became more pastoral in form, framing its expansion as an ethical project devised to redeem the colonized, the work of missionaries became almost paradigmatic for the imperial enterprise. At the forefront of the spiritual invasion of India, they represented pastoral power in its purest or at least most literal form.
A central document in the articulation of the new pastoral paradigm was
Charles Grant s (1746-1823) Observations on the State of Society among the Asiatic Subjects of Great Britain (1792). Grant wrote the essay at the height of the Hastings debacle in order to persuade his friend Henry Dundas, President of the East India Company s Board of Control, to allow missionaries to proselytize in India. It was circulated semi-privately in the 1790s and then published during the Charter debates of 1813.[138] In classic form, the text displaces despotism from the state onto religion. It does this both substantively and by way of a revealing simile. Grant proclaims that the Hindoo s understanding is chained and kept in perpetual imprisonment, like dreaded rivals for power in the East, who deprived of their eyes, and immured in dungeons, receive poisoned provisions from the gaoler s hands. [139] Just as the Oriental despot imprisons his subjects bodies, the Oriental priest imprisons his subjects minds.
In his Observations, Grant claimed that the Hindu religion was nothing but a system of delusive fraud even more odious than that of Catholic Europe. The brahmins are the true idols of this system, and they must be shattered (OSS, 62-63). As Grant goes on to explain, Nothing is more plain, than that this whole fabric is the work of a crafty and imperious priesthood, who feigned a divine revelation and appointment, to invest their own order, in perpetuity, with the most absolute empire over the civil state of the Hindoos, as well as over their minds (44-45). An original cadre of crafty priests delegated proxy princes to take on the tedious work of statecraft, while retaining all substantial power for themselves. They thus ensured that, in India at least, states were superfluous to the actual business of rule. Even when the Hindoos lost the dominion of their own country, the influence of their religion, and their priests, remained (74). As Grant puts it, the one complex system of the Hindoo religion had impressed a principle of despotism into the very frame of society (44). The influence of the Enlightenment theory of religious imposture, detailed in Chapter One, should be clear. Its implications for the colonial context, however, bear pointing out. According to Grant, a singular species of despotism haunts Hindustan (OSS, 46). This despotism is pervasive, inscribed into the fabric of society, and thus largely divorced from the apparatus of state. Grant uses the figure of the despotic priest to retheorize power as something diffused throughout the social body. The priest thus prods the reconstitution of imperial power noted by Dirks. If the micro-circuitry of power depends on religion, the British must intervene in religion to assert their sovereignty in
India.
At the end of his Observations, Grant poses a decisive question. The Company must decide whether it will leave its subjects in darkness, error, and moral turpitude or whether it will communicate to them the light of truth. It can wink at the stupidity which we deem profitable to us; and as governors, be in effect the conservators of that system which deceives the people. Or, it can explain the divine principles of moral and religious truth, which have raised us in the scale of being, and are the foundation of all real goodness and happiness. In other words, it can assume the mantle of either priest or pastor. Priestly power would cynically maintain sacred hierarchies that it believes to be illusions ( la Hastings perhaps). Pastoral power, on the other hand, protests against religious authority and enjoins the formation of autonomous liberal subjects. The line between priest and pastor, however, was not often clear: both extended their rule by asserting authority over both mind and body. Imperial rhetoric vociferously condemned crafty priests in order to disavow the spiritual rule that was increasingly central to imperial governance.
The printing press was taken to be the major instrument for the production of liberal subjects, whether in a secular or a Christian modality. Presses promised to redeem the deluded multitude by exposing the sacred pretensions of charlatanic priests, as well as by remaking the crowd as a critical public through the solitary discipline of reading. These notions, common in Anglo-Indian writing from the nineteenth century, fit snugly within what Michael Warner has termed the WhigMcLuhanite model of print history. This paradigm, influential since at least the eighteenth century, attributes to the print medium an ontological status prior to culture while simultaneously tethering print to a culturally peculiar narrative about emancipation from ecclesiastical and civil tyranny. [140] The model thus deftly naturalizes the teleology of Enlightenment: the bourgeois social order spontaneously unfolds from the material inevitabilities of print, having already been lodged there in potentia, a genie in a bottle.
Warner resists this techno-determinism by detailing the cultural codes that came to determine and define public speech. The concept publication as a political condition of utterance was the organizing principle for print publics: it was enmeshed with the commercial structures of the print market, with the legal regulation of authorship, and with the mutual constitution of private and political life.[141] Additionally, it highlighted a novel sort of assembly. Unlike the public of the customary order, which was always incarnated in a relation between persons and which found its highest expression in church and town meetings, the public of print discourse was an abstract public never localizable in any relation between persons. Ghostly though this abstract public may have seemed, it remained reliant on a very material base: the print artifact itself. In principle, print artifacts in their routine dispersion circulate without limit and thereby convene a public of unprecedented size. The hazy boundaries of this potentially unlimited public only serve to underscore its apparent universality. Even as print artifacts found this public and remain its material metonyms, they are also constituted by it: print artifacts gained their symbolic potency through conventions of discourse that allowed them to be political in a special way. [142]
This theory of print media, central to the modern political and social order, was a favorite of British writers in nineteenth century India. At first, it was mostly the
province of missionaries. The grand era of missionary publicity in India might be said
to have begun in 1792, when William Carey arrived in Bengal and published his Enquiry into the Obligations of Christians to Use Means for the Conversion of Heathens. Carey s semilicit press at the Danish colony of Serampore (Srirampur) had a decisive influence on the publications to come. The work of the Serampore trio (William Carey, William Ward, and Joshua Marshman) provided a template for the radically expanded missionary scene that emerged after 1813, when changes to the East India Company s charter lifted the ban on proselytizing. Indeed, the intensification of missionary efforts in the years after 1813 significantly altered the modes of publicity available to missionaries concerned with India. Documents that had been circulated privately as late as the 1790s (Bishop Reginald Heber s journal, Charles Grant s Observations ) now found new life in the open pages of the press.[143][144]
The Missionary Register, cited heavily in this chapter, was the first of the major English missionary periodicals, entering publication in January 1813. Rev. Joseph Pratt of the Church Missionary Society (CMS) launched the Register to awaken the Public to the state of the Heathen World, by giving information derived from all quarters. [145] Copies were sent free of charge to CMS members who collected at least one shilling per week in donations, as well as to select members of other societies. Between 1814 and
1824, the Register s monthly circulation rose from 5000 to 7500; actual readership was likely larger still, as copies were commonly passed among friends or read aloud in churches. Its success during its early years is indexed by the 1817 decision to start including woodcut illustrations of exotic subjects in each issue. The Register ultimately ceased publication in 1855.[146] Periodicals like the Missionary Register were important disseminators of other texts, as they routinely featured extracts from books, diaries, and other periodicals. Rev. William Bowley s journal was especially popular during the peak years of the Missionary Register s run (roughly 1817-1829). As the Register wrote in the early 1820s, it is by Journals of this nature that Christians at home become familiar with the habits of thinking among the Heathen and learn duly to appreciate the difficulties of Missionaries, and to feel and pray for them. [147]
The interpenetration of print periodicals with less overtly public literary forms raises several questions, most pertinently that of whether these more private modes of composition did in fact presume a depersonalized, general audience. Several scholars have argued that, in the context of eighteenth century European letters, they certainly did; or, at least, by cultivating a distinct private sphere of cultural endeavor, such genres helped produce social forms that contributed to the emergence of the democratic nation-state and its mode of political engagement. In the present context, a similar condition seems to structure private avowals of belief. If the Rev. Bowley kept his diary with the express purpose of eventual publication, then this most quintessentially interior literary form comes to presuppose the unlimited reading public as its proper audience. In the act of writing, interiority and exteriority merge, and belief comes to function as a social fact, the product of intersubjective relations. If missionary publications seem intent on producing divisions between the private and the public or, more precisely, on using the print public to reconfigure the private domain of subjective interiority this is no mistake. A major plank of the missionary program was the reform of Hindoo subjectivities. Where once the mad multitude thronged heathen temples, henceforth a rational public would peruse the pages of print media. Where once tropical bodies courted disease and danger, henceforth silent minds would convene a far more spiritual assembly. The former mode of collectivity was thought to promote ecclesiastical tyranny; the latter would usher in bourgeois egalitarianism. To redeem India, its multitudes would have to be remade as publics.
To get a sense for how missionary writers defined their project (and, perhaps more importantly, what they defined it against), one could do worse than to examine their descriptions of Hindu festivals, pilgrimages, and processions. The general sense in this literature is that the seething multitude is the primary social form hailed by Hinduism. This presumption structured several of the most noted controversies of the period, such as the debates about suttee or the wheel of the Juggernaut at Puri. [148]
William Ward, the most prolific member of the Serampore trio, confessed to hiding during Calcutta s Durga puja. Festival-goers, alongside their brahminical ringleaders in crime, would scandalously exhibit licentious images to the public gaze. In order to avoid visual corruption, one should either stay home or, as Ward s brahman friend
Gopal apparently preferred, hide
behind one of the pillars of the temple. [149]
Alexander Duff had a similar reaction to the same festival. He noted the numbers without numbers of crazed devotees who ripped to shreds the m$rti of the goddess, and he fell mute before the inexpressible multitude. Here language entirely fails. Imagination itself must sink down with wings collapsed; utterly baffled in the effort to conceive the individualities and the groupings of an assemblage composed of such varied magnitudes. If the mobile assemblage of the crowd stymies representation, it also serves to excite speech: the unspeakable horrors of the multitude animated the print publics convened by missionary writers. They not only provided the motive for missionary work; the figure of the crowd allowed missionary writing to cultivate literary effects that they might otherwise forbid themselves. Routine protestations that they would rather not describe the horrors of heathenism allowed these writers to disavow their investment in salacious description. Such descriptions also, and perhaps more importantly, served to emphasize the subjective distance between the faceless multitude and the literate individual. Duff, for instance, reported having stood on the banks of the Ganges, surrounded by the deluded multitudes engaged in ablutions. There on the banks he came to feel his own solitude in the midst of the teeming throng, and due to this sense of solitude, a cold sensation of horror has crept through the soul. [150]
In addition to reflecting on their own literary task obliquely via descriptions of devotional multitudes, British missionary writers also wrote explicitly about print media and its effects. In 1792, Charles Grant lauded print s ability to demonstrate the great use of reason by the British (OSS, 78). Thirty years later, John Bentley argued that the press would free India from the fetters of ignorance and superstition just as it had done for the nations of Europe. [151] As a rule, the triumphs of the press must in all countries bear a very great affinity. [152] The medium is naturally a mighty engine of improvement that awakens and arouses the human mind; in its mighty progress, it subdues the inveterate prejudices of ages, annihilates error, and not only elicits truth, but disposes the mind to welcome it in all its brightness. [153] Above all, print media has the power to unseat despotic priests. The press pries open doors of knowledge barred by the founders of religion, who rely on ignorance to ensure the blind submission of the populace. It will undo the priests because it will transform the natives into a reading people [154]:
The framers of the popular superstition could not have foreseen, that in the lapse of years, there would be introduced into their country and nourished by their countrymen, an engine of improvement, which had dispelled delusion in every country which enjoyed it an engine which would necessarily unfold to the view of all India the grounds on which their spiritual belief rests. Their system was not contrived with a view to this future contingency, and we strongly suspect that it will not long hold out against the increase of light and knowledge.
Print breaks the charm of idolatry, and, once the spell is broken, its disjointed and disorganized fragments can never be re-assembled into the same uniform and powerful system. [155]
Triumphant claims about the rise of reading among the Hindoos recurred regularly in missionary and other publications of the period.[156] For example, an 1830 report by the American Board of Missions claimed that decreased temple attendance in Bombay had been caused by increasing literacy and the consequent decline in the brahmins ascendency and influence over the mass of the people. [157] However, complacency about the assured benefits of print was also often disrupted by a pervasive concern that India s proliferating presses could produce other effects. The popular publication of gross mythological tales led one writer to condemn the
corruption and prostitution of the Press. [158] As another writer opined, should the press become the auxiliary of Superstition, then the greatest engine of improvement yet discovered by man would be fundamentally perverted.[159] If some missionary writers fretted about the content of the print media, others fretted about the mode of distribution of print artifacts. To borrow a phrase from Homi Bhabha, missionaries thought that Indians would convert signs into wonders, bringing biblical texts back into the magical economy of material religion.[160] As Bhabha has argued, scenes of native converts marveling at Bibles indicated the parodic potential of imperial stereotypes and thus also the instability of imperial ideology. I would add that they further indicate the degree to which the conception of print publics as disembodied arenas could run afoul of the material circuits of print distribution and consumption. An overly eager desire for print objects undermined a print mythology that deemphasized mass distribution by insisting on the priority of lonely consumption. In the words of one writer: eagerness for Tracts is sometimes overwhelming a hundred hands lifted up at an instant, while one cries I will have a book another, I can read: let me have one another, I wish to get one for my brother, who will read it to me: thus 50, 80, 100, or more Tracts are occasionally distributed. [161] Despite the missionary s effort to claim this scene as evidence of print s popularity, his sense of the overwhelming demand for print objects suggest that, in
the act of distribution, the feared frenzy of the multitude returns. This was not a problem unique to India; it was rather inherent to the ideological constitution of the print public more generally. However, the colonial context does lend this particular episode its precise political contours. The British missionary, in act of bequeathing tracts, loses some control over the crowd that the tracts had been designed to discipline.
In fact, missionary writings attest to the constant struggle for control that structured missionaries relations with the multitudes that they had set forth to convert. Skepticism was often the site for this contestation: missionary writers arrogated Indians critical attitudes and offhand dismissals of religious authorities to their own cause, registering the existence of Indian skeptics while tendentiously using their criticisms as support for the master thesis of native credulity. In the process, such texts came to rely on the figure of the subaltern skeptic. This figure was subaltern in a precise sense. As Gyan Prakash has defined, the subaltern erupts from within the system of dominance and marks its limit from within such that its externality to dominant systems of knowledge and power surface inside the system of dominance, but only as an intimation, as a trace of that which eludes the dominant discourse. [162] Subaltern skeptics in missionary texts straddle the limit of pastoral power, reflecting the liberal mode of subjectivity enjoined by Evangelicals and others, while also intimating the existence of other histories of skepticism.
For instance, in December 1830 the Missionary Register printed a story about
Atmaran, a native convert from Benares. Told in the first person, it narrated
Atmaran s disillusionment with Hindu ritual and Hindu miracle during a pilgrimage to Puri. The tale begins with a Padree Sahib preaching in a Benares bazaar. He announces to the gathered crowd that Juggernaut could not save them from hell for, at bottom, he was all deception. Atmaran heard this comment and, encouraged by his friends, resolved to travel to Puri to determine for himself the truth of the Padri s allegations of divine fraud.
Atmaran planned to assess two of the Lord Jaggan!th s famed miracles. First, he would ascertain whether the god s chariot (rath) moved forward by itself, propelled by supernal powers. Second, he would visit the temple kitchen to investigate its miraculous rice, which was said to cook backwards. The cooks would stack twenty pots of rice on a single fire and, contrary to natural law, the top pot s rice would finish first. Atmaran formulated a hypothesis that could be tested empirically: if this [the miracles] were the case, Juggernaut must be true. And so the young man, in order to be quite satisfied in my own mind regarding the power of Juggernaut to save, set forth on his arduous journey. Several months later, weary and emaciated, he arrived in Puri to wait for the annual festival.
Eventually, Atmaran s moment arrived. The Lord Jaggan!th s chariot issued from the temple, and Atmaran squeezed through the crowd so that he might stand near to the procession. I waited a good while: but, at last, there came running several thousands of men, who took hold on the car ropes; and, after a deal of flogging and pulling, the car began to grate on its wheels. When I saw this, then I said, This is all a lie. He asked a man near him in the crowd why the god did not move on his own; the man replied that it was not his pleasure.
Atmaran now only waited to ascertain the truth about the rice cooking. He made his way to the Idol s cook-rooms; but soon discovered that, while the bottom vessel was quite ready; the uppermost was quite cold. Having found the miracles to be false, Atmaran concluded that the god must be false too: I was now quite satisfied, that what the Padree had said was quite true, and that Juggernaut was all deception. Before returning to Benares to seek salvation from the Padree, Atmaran rushed out of the kitchen and into the street to remonstrate the local pandits ( Pundahs ) for their duplicity in deluding the people with lies. Their reply to the skeptical youth challenges the clarity of his disenchanted sight: Everybody sees that he is going by himself now; but the fact is, that you are so sinful that you can see nothing; and it is for your sins that Juggernaut has blinded your eyes that you cannot see.
Atmaran s simple tale was collected by one Mr. Lacey, a Baptist missionary.
Lacey glossed the narrative as illustrative of the deceptions by which the Native Superstition is upheld. He praises Atmaran as a man who seeks for evidence, and feels its importance; and who, when he finds evidence, yields to its authority. Atmaran s enemy and opposite is the priest who, in his insolent effrontery, tried to persuade the man out of his senses. [163] Atmaran comes to stands in for scientific empiricism, and the Pundah for the retrograde doctrinalism of institutional religion. According to Lacey, the failed miracle proves the truth of Christianity and the falsity of Hinduism; the non-duped will let their eyes lead them to Christ.
Atmaran s tale demonstrates that the subjective position of the native skeptic was easily co-opted by British polemicists and thus rendered subaltern in the sense suggested above. At one level, Atmaran is simply a cipher, a literary character fully a function of Lacey s missionary narrative. The ideological use of this character is completely transparent to the postcolonial reader: Atmaran dramatizes the move into the system of dominance. The subaltern can speak, but only after he has taken on the language of the colonizer. However, there is surely also a trace here of an actual man named Atmaran, whose history and whose subjectivity cannot be reduced to the missionary narrative, but who rather inscribes that narrative s limit from within the narrative itself
In some of these texts, the co-opted stories of the colonized seem to put themselves in quotation marks against the will of the missionary writer, resisting and recording the effort to read them as evidence of colonial credulity. For instance, when a group of yogis casually confessed that their austerities were performed to earn a livelihood, or when brahmans reciting a Bengali Ramayana did not hesitate to avow that their views were entirely mercenary, they presumably did not mean to confess to dastardly greed. Likewise, when the audience of that same Ramayana agreed that the Gooroos were out to get their money rather than leading them into the way of salvation, they were surely just conceding that specialists who recite the epic should be paid for their labors (and, perhaps, admitting disinterest in the theological business of salvation ).[164] Others among the missionaries interlocutors seem to have gone so far as to celebrate a good swindle and admire the skill of the huckster (an especially clever
stratagem might be appreciated with a cry of Well done! ).[165]
Occasionally, missionary journals would print stories that had likely already enjoyed substantial popularity in networks of oral circulation (that is, what would later come to be classified as folklore). Such tales, playful and constitutively suspicious of those in power, permit the clever poor to dupe the credulous rich. One comic story tells of Praun Poory, A Hindoo Fakeer who convinces a king that his ulcer is the mystic source of his royal sovereignty.[166] Another more elaborate tale of two Imposters and a credulous Monarch introduces a poor brahman who, with his nephew s help, devises a plot to dupe a king. He grows his hair and nails long, hides in a cave, and sends the nephew to tell the king that his guru, who commenced austerities during Rama s reign, has just awakened from meditation. The pretended Ascetic, speaking in Sanskrit, proceeds to trick the king out of a fortune.
The editor packaged the story as an Illustration of Hindoo Craft and Credulity, claiming it as a striking illustration of the cunning by which the credulous Natives are led away. It ought to stimulate the zeal of Christians to deliver them from the gross delusions under which they are held in bondage. However, he further claims that this uncle and nephew team were so notorious for every species of fraud, that their names continue even to this day to be used proverbially, in many parts of the country, to denote a fraudulent combination. [167] The latter laudation, amused with the successful scam, persists even in the Missionary Register, where the tale is appropriated for a different public and for different ends. Although the journal tries to co-opt the skepticism of authority rife in oral literatures in order to bolster the stock narrative of Hindu credulity, this particular tale seems instead to attest to skeptical traditions not reducible to the theory of religious imposture.
The Secular Press
By the 1850s, the journalistic sector was well developed enough to lay claim to the narrative of print modernity. The major papers of western India, for instance, celebrated their social function by adopting heroic mottos to emblazon on their front pages. The Poona Observer lifted its epigraph from Daniel Defoe: if the impartial writer dares venture upon the dangerous precipice of telling unbiased truth let him expect martyrdom on both sides, and then he may go on fearless. The Bombay Gazette preferred Milton: Give me the liberty to know, to utter, to argue freely according to conscience, above all others.
Papers also regularly celebrated the mobility of print artifacts. In 1857, the Oriental News estimated that the entire newspaper press of the world reaches about two hundred million of its inhabitants, or one-fourth of the adult population of the globe ; in its unintermitted intercourse, it is traversing every region of the earth
(this article itself, reprinted from the New York Times attests to this global circulation).[168] As another article noted, even nations that had tried to shield themselves from the intrusions of British imperialism and its information order had come under the sway of the English press: Even in Khatmandu, in the very depths of the Himalayas, and with the real ruler of a country in which assassination is a virtue, English opinion as represented by the press has an influence. [169]
Journalists were often quite forthright about the disciplinary functions of the press and its ability to adopt and diffuse the functions like those of the policeman or the priest. As the Bombay Times and Journal of Commerce described the role of print media:
The press penetrates every nook and corner of society; it searches out and apprehends the most recluse and the most unsocial in the city and in the field, in the palace and in the cottage; it steals unawares upon the guilty and rebukes the conscience; it is an officer of justice who does not need to seek out the criminal, for the criminal himself seeks out the officer, and takes him to his home as a friend and a companion. Unlike the pulpit, the press preaches at home and in secret; the reader need not dress and walk one mile or five to church, in order to be addressed by the preacher of the press, for the preacher comes to him, and goes to bed with him, if he pleases, or takes a walk with him in the garden, or by the river side, and pours into the intellectual ears of his vision the words which he has the commission to utter.[170]
In other words, a newspaper lodges a priest inside the head of its reader, shifting the locus of command to produce exactly the sort of self-governing subject that J. S. Mill had in mind. Print would remake the souls of the colonized and, in doing so, upend priestly religion.
Despite their apparent confidence in print media s ineluctable effects, however,
Indian newspapers remained dissatisfied with the contours of the colonial public. They compared the Indian public sphere to the paradigmatic English model, and India consistently came up lacking.[171] The conservative Bombay Saturday Review complained that there is no public opinion proper in India: colonial functionaries lack real public feeling and so can form only a little-boy public; a public in the earliest stages of arriving at the consciousness of being so. In India, the Review writes, the journal represents the naked principle of publicity only, no more. [172] Other papers complained the Indian public was not properly undifferentiated. A common view was that the Press of this country certainly is not the press of the people ; every press between the Himalayas and Cape Cormorin, is a Caste Press. They are all the organs of Caste interests, and they do not write for the universal people. The article implies that, because its public is fractured, India cannot properly lay claim to nationhood.[173] A retort published in the same paper, however, insisted that Anglo-Indian publics were just as fractured. As all of the English in India are in Service, all of their papers are beholden to different interests (military, commercial, indigo, etc). There is no such thing in existence in India as a Public, in the European sense of the term. [174] As a Bombay Telegraph and Courier article put it, Young India cannot yet succeed in producing anything better than a feeble parody of the English institution of free speech. [175] If
Indian publics were taken as parodic of English paradigms, this seems to have derived in part from the continued importance of the gup in the bazaar. [176] In other words, if Indian public life was a parody of the eminently English institution of free speech, this was because Indian publics exceeded the sorts of speech that the English were inclined to read as free free speech being a mode of utterance constrained by the legal and cultural norms of English liberalism.
Free speech was also conditioned by the economic imperatives of the print media market competitive conditions exemplified by the insane rivalry among the dailies in Bombay and elsewhere.[177] In 1861, the Bombay Times, the Bombay Standard, and the Telegraph and Courier were amalgamated to form the Times of India. Other papers were acutely aware of the merger and its effects on the journalists involved; as the
Poona Observer reported, the Times of India bought out the Telegraph and Courier s editor George Craig and paid him to move to Australia.[178] During the coming years, the Bombay press would be dominated by the rivalry between the new Times and the Bombay Gazette. Newspapers often heaped caustic criticisms on their rivals. The Bombay Gazette, for instance, called the Times of India a drug, recently thrown upon this market, with
mephitic fumes and vapors emanating from the dregs that occupy his correspondence columns. The Times of India is running amuck, and under its intoxicating influence, so will the Bombay public.[179]
The rivalry between the two major Bombay dailies was joined by other rivalries, such as the one between the Poona Observer and its little brother, the Deccan Herald.[180] As the Observer once noted: We have a great dislike to a newspaper warfare, more especially when the foe we have to fight with is a lighter weight than ourselves. [181] Such disparagement sometimes verged on actual slander, as when the Oriental News alleged that both the Bombay Gazette and the Bombay Times had accepted bribes.[182] Rivalries were heightened by the regular poaching of material. Newspapers subscribed to competitor titles, even printing official lists of all the papers they received.[183] Cross-subscriptions enabled widespread cribbing. As the Poona Observer complained during a slow news season, [e]verything is stagnant, nothing lively, and the bother of it is that all other editors being in the same fix, we cannot even crib an article worth the trouble from any of our contemporaries. Quarrels often arose as a result of this practice.[184] Newspapers commentary on the newspaper business was so ubiquitous as to warrant its own species of meta-commentary. The Poona Observer even published a satirical tale about a meeting of the newspapers.[185]As the Bombay Gazette wrote, we are sure the public, or at least our public, does not care for shop quarrels. [186]
The publishing of sensational stories played an important part in these rivalries, piquing public interest and allowing those papers that refrained from sensationalism to claim the moral high ground over those who indulged. As one writer reflected, regarding gossip about bigamists and nepotism:
almost anything will tickle the ears of the crowd. At one time a talking fish charms them with its eloquence, or a Home imbues them with the belief that the furniture might be persuaded to go out and take a walk, while the rooms were being swept: spirit-rapping or horse-taming, prayers or pugilism, rareeshows or revivals each and all are alike welcomed by a stolid John Bull.[187]
Scandal, as we shall see, extended to matters of religion. The salacious Maharaj Libel
Case, which both the Times of India and the Bombay Gazette covered intensively in of
1861-62, likely owed much of its fame to scandal-mongering journalistic competition
(Chapter 3). Nor was the case the only cause c l bre to thrill Indian reading publics in 1861-62: the Lucknow Libel Case and the Nil Durpan affair were both popular topics. As the Poona Observer said of the Times of India, When it gets hold of a subject of temporary importance, it harps upon it until long after public interest in it has passed away. [188]
Debates about the shortcomings of the Indian public were often motivated by the rivalries among papers. An 1861-62 quarrel among the Bombay Saturday Review, the
Times of India, and the Bombay Gazette pondered whether Bombay could be said to possess a proper public. As the conservative Review put it, We want a public which shall be no counterfeit. [189] Bombay s public ailed, the paper opined, because the Gazette was a spiritless newspaper dummy, a large body, containing the orthodox number of columns filled with printed matter, and having no life or soul within it. The Times of India, meanwhile, it traduced with a quotation from John Stuart Mill about the collective mediocrity of public opinion: Their thinking is done for them by men much like themselves, addressing them or speaking in their name, on the spur of the moment, through the newspapers. [190]
As the Bombay Gazette once complained, the secular press has hitherto been too secular ; the press should, the article explains, assume the mantle of the preacher.[191] As this quip makes clear, even Anglo-Indian periodicals without explicit missionary ties made regular reference to religion. Elsewhere, for instance, the Gazette advocated for the government adoption of the New Testament as a moral code for society.[192] The Poona Observer, however, was probably the most unabashed journalistic champion of British Christianity, and it used religion to advance its own cause. For instance, when the Times of India suggested that a society be established for the improvement of public morals, the Observer countered that there was only one such society, and it was founded about
1800 years ago.[193] The Poona Observer also held anti-Catholic views, and this led to its
enthusiastic embrace of the polemics of priestcraft. It railed against European Popedom and the witchery and trickery of priestcraft. [194] It cheered at the instability of the Italian states.[195] Some criticisms were poetical (e.g. Tom the Snob s Some millions are supported by the fraud/ And therefore the mistaken notion laud ).[196] Others drew analogies between the Protestant Reformation and assaults on nineteenth century Hinduism. In such claims, the line between the secular and the missionary press became nebulous indeed.
Scottish missionary Alexander Duff (1806-1878) included a curious equivocation in his 1840 sketch of the gigantic system of Hinduism. Our present purpose, he assures the reader, is not to expose, but simply to exhibit the system of Hinduism. Duff quickly goes on to explain that Hinduism s best confutation must be the extravagance and absurdity of its tenets ; that, in short, to exhibit Hinduism is to expose it.[197] The following discussion will dissect the major assumption behind Duff s equivocation: that public speech about false religion undermines that religion, that to make Hinduism public to expose it is to undo Hinduism.
The rhetoric of exposure was pervasive in English writing about Indian religions, dating at least as far back as Charles Grant s 1792 Observations. One of Grant s central assertions is that false religion shuns fair examination. He argues that the Hindoos err because they are ignorant; and their errors have never fairly been laid before them, and he urges the East India Company to deploy reason and argument in combating these errors (OSS, 77). According to Grant, if the gross absurdities of Heathenism were to be clearly exposed... their abettors would find themselves extremely at a loss to defend by argument assumptions wholly destitute of evidence, internal or external (83). For Grant, the public sphere is a discursive arena characterized by reasoned argument, determinative of truth, the work of which is to weaken the fabric of falsehood (79).
Crucially for Grant, Protestant Christianity is the one religion that can thrive in this rational public: Christianity gains by being examined. It courts the light (OSS, 90). This claim, of course would not hold true on the Catholic Continent, where that pure religion has been changed into a mystery of imposture and corruption, itself the perfect mirror of Hinduism (63). In Grant s imperial imaginary, Protestant Christianity was the modern religion, operating in the mode of publicity, and Hinduism (with its Catholic cousin) was the anti-modern religion, operating under the tyranny of wily brahmans in the mode of concealment (78-79). Or, as one later commentator put it, the entire Hindu system was admirably adapted to illustrate the Roman Catholic motto, viz. Ignorance is the mother of devotion. [198] The promise of the missionaries was that the darkness of this anti-modern religiosity would wither in the curative light of the rational Protestant public (77).
The rhetoric of exposure invoked by Grant, Duff, and others relied on a mode of magical thinking. Magic has long been defined as involving an irrational belief in the efficacy of mere words. Incantations, mantras, and spells do not merely signify real things; they really change those things.[199] Ernst Cassirer, for instance, has argued that in the magical worldview the two factors, thing and signification, are undifferentiated because they merge, grow together, concresce in an immediate unity. For magic, there is no such thing as mere mimesis, mere signification. [200] Just so, the epistemology of exposure presupposes the omnipotence of the printed word, investing ink with an nearly magical power to shatter belief. If false religion rules by enchantment, printed speech breaks the spell with its equally potent counter-magic.
To be sure, words are never entirely inert entities, nor separate from the things that they signify. Rather, as speech act theorists have amply attested, words always and inevitably do things. This was certainly the case for nineteenth century exhibitions of Hinduism. As scholars have repeatedly argued, colonial representations of Indian religions invented Hinduism. Or, less starkly put, the colonial contest over the representation of religion precipitated a series of shifts in belief and practice that enabled the consolidation of a syndicated Hinduism as one of the world religions. In some ways Duff is more honest than those who exhibited Hinduism both before and after him (William Jones, Monier Monier-Williams): he knew that description was never innocent, that to represent Hinduism was to change it.
Indeed, my interest in Duff s equation of exhibition with exposure stems in part from the ways it anticipates the work of J. L. Austin. In his influential lecture series How to Do Things with Words, Austin developed the concept of the performative utterance. We generally tend to think of our utterances as descriptive or constantive in nature (e.g. The sky is blue. ) Austin calls attention to a different class of utterances that, when they are done right, actually alter conditions in the world. The classic example of such a performative utterance is the I do uttered at a wedding ceremony. To say I do is not just to say something; it is to do something (to become a lawfully wedded husband or wife). As such, it is a speech act. Over the course of his lectures, Austin assiduously erodes the presumed distinction between constative and performative utterances, alleging that we do things with words far more often than we realize. In some ways, this is precisely Alexander Duff s point as well: to think that one can simply exhibit Hinduism is na ve; one also always does more than this. Where I depart from Duff (and depart dramatically) is in his claim that by exhibiting Hinduism, he actually exposes it. Duff is right to think that his description of Hinduism is also performative (it does things); he is wrong in thinking that what his words do might be characterized as exposure. The illocutionary conditions of his utterance are, in Austin s terms, infelicitious: exposure is generally not a type of performative speech available to a print artifact.[201]
As discussed in the first chapter, the trope of exposure had been central to charlatan tales since the raucous raillery of the English Enlightenment. Early modern treatises on religious fraud, like those of Charles Blount (1654-1693) and Bernard le Boivier de Fontenelle (1657-1757), described the theatrical tricks that ancient priests and oracles had used to awe the masses. These texts circulated alongside popular enlightened entertainments, like models of fake oracles, which incorporated sight and sound into their theatrical apparatus. Treatises and theatrical entertainments were all, to use Simon During s phrase, part of the same magical assemblage ; however, the trope of exposure operated differently in the different sectors of that assemblage.[202] Texts could not lift the curtain to expose the backstage treachery of priests in the same way that theatrical entertainments could. If they made considerable use of visual tropes, they did so to bolster their own claims to authority, in the process propagating a productive confusion between the verbal and the visual, between print publics and theatrical ones.
Even so, the trope of exposure was very important to early modern imposture theorists, who repeatedly averred that the printing press would necessarily extinguish the Hindu religion. By translating scriptures from Sanskrit into Bengali, it was said that Indian publishers were opening those scriptures to the comprehension of all and thus hastening Hindooism in its progress to the grave. This is the Whig-McLuhanite paradigm in full force. Whatsoever doth make manifest, is light: and the effect of this publication will unconsciously be the exposure of the perplexity and confusion, the darkness and cruelty, of the whole system. The more it is exposed, the sooner will it fall into deserved oblivion [203] Such predications, of course, proved massively false. Vernacular translations of classical texts did change Hindu practice and Hindu public culture in important ways, but not according to the plotline of exposure prescribed by this theory of media effects. Print artifacts cannot expose a charlatan (or a religion) like theatrical entertainments can; they can only proliferate veils of representation.
To
conclude, I would suggest that the same constitutive contradiction structures
the tale of Atmran summarized above. The Missionary Register s account
of Atmaran s disillusionment relays theatrical exposures into a print
periodical, where it inevitably has a different set of effects. The
Missionary Register may have hoped that its pages could expose Hinduism,
but although visual tropes and narratives might have reinforced the journal s
authority, they could never produce the visual clarity available to conventional
(that is, embodied) publics. Moreover, Atmaran s tale suggests a further
limitation on the narrative of exposure, even in such contexts: as the Pundah
reminds Atmaran, what we cannot see is often as real as what we can see. This,
as Slavoj &i ek has suggested, is why the non-duped err (see Introduction).
Atmaran does not have to conclude from the apparent falsity of the miracles
that Hinduism is false; much less that Christianity is true. This presumes not
only the discursive coherence of the reified and mutually exclusive religions
Hinduism and Christianity, but also the polemic association of the former
with its immanent and the latter with its transcendent dimensions. As &i ek
puts it, the stepping out of (what we experience as) ideology is the very form
of our enslavement to it, and this is amply demonstrated by the narrative of
print media s exposure of false religion.[204]
For after you abandoned, as you did, for my sake, the world, the Vedas, your very Selves and all that was yours, O helpless ones, in order to follow me, I worshipped you, though my worship was not visible, when I disappeared. And so you, my loved ones, should not be angry with me, your Lover.
Bh"gavata Pur"!a [205]
Better have no opinion of God at all, than an injurious one
Francis Bacon[206]
The Maharaj Libel Case of 1862 thrilled scandalmongers throughout India with its tales of a Gujarati guru gone bad, earning acclaim as the greatest trial of modern times since the trial of Warren Hastings. [207] The controversial contest between reformminded journalist Karsand!s M+,j$ and Jadun!thj$ Brizratanj$, a leader or Maharaj of the Pu()im!rg$ Vai(*avas, had been brewing for years in the Gujarati press. It was not until an especially umbrageous 1860 article spurred Jadunathji to sue Mulji for libel, however, that their row went national with the leap into English. The article in question not only denounced the Pu()im!rg as heterodox, a latter-day corruption of the originary Vedic religion; it accused Jadunathji of foisting himself on his female devotees. Although Jadunathji had hoped that the Bombay High Court would clear his good name, he was sorely mistaken. After a grueling three-month hearing, the British judges decided that Mulji s libel was justified. As alleged, the Pu()im!rg was held to be a heterodox debasement of authentic Hinduism, and Jadunathji a libidinous sham of a spiritual guide. The guru stood convicted of sexual and textual corruption.
In this chapter, I will consider the Maharaj Libel Case as a point of application for the imposture theory of religion. From the start, Mulji s allegations against the Maharaj had ventured a critical comparison to Christianity: in their tyranny (julm), he averred, the popes were the maharajas of Europe.[208] In casting himself as an Indian Luther, Mulji scripted a drama with scandalous appeal. The Maharaj Libel Case centered on what David Haberman has termed the ontological hierarchy of guru and disciple.[209][210] The court and the press both sought to sever that hierarchical bond, and in order to do so they entered it into the stock narrative of priestly imposture. As I have suggested, this narrative had a single fixed ending: priestly exposure, disenchantment, the end of illusion. Scripting religion as imposture was a way to constrain religion s public possibilities. The rhetoric of priestly imposture was rife throughout the trial. Consider Mulji s attorney s defense plea: it is wicked and impious thing for a mere man to pretend to be a God or to be capable of begetting a God or to practice impostures in that behalf on any people. [211] Or the closing remarks of one of the judges: We must suppose the case of a weak and blinded people; a rapacious and libidinous priesthood; a God whose most popular attributes are his feats of sexual prowess (MLC, 478-79). In the following discussion, I want to call that juridical supposition into question. What procedures were applied in order to produce this as a case of a blinded people and a rapacious priesthood ? How else might the guru-disciple relationship be imagined?
The chapter s argument is as follows. During the Maharaj Libel Affair, court and press worked in tandem to undermine the sovereignty of Gujarati caste polities; the court did so by criminalizing the polities efforts at self-governance, the press by opening caste polities to the powers of publicity. Both fixated on religious leaders as icons of caste power. There was an additional tension, albeit a suppressed one, between court and press: Karsandas Mulji s journalistic criticism of the guru was co-opted by the court. Mulji espoused an oppositional heterodoxy; he amplified contradictions internal to Hindu, and especially Pu()im!rg$, tradition in order to articulate an immanent critique of that tradition. The Bombay High Court, on the other hand, used such heterodox dissension as an excuse to extend its own ostensibly secular rule. The transcendent colonial state would arbitrate among competing religious communities and, in the process, come to manage religion.
As many scholars have noted, the Maharaj Libel Case exemplifies how the British state came to administer orthodoxy, by reducing religion to a set of canonical texts easily assimilated to the bureaucratic procedures of colonial rule. I use the imposture theory to call this process into sharper relief. The court attempted, in Max Weber s terms, to routinize the guru s charisma. The guru-disciple bond, with its unpredictable affective intensities, would be severed. In its place, a system of regularities, of texts, codes, and bureaucratic procedures, would emerge as the authentic Hinduism. Although the imposture theory decried the multitude s alleged credulity, the colonial state apparatus remained ambivalent about the powers of belief. As I will suggest, events like the Maharaj Libel Case aimed not to eliminate belief entirely, but rather to re-discipline it, by steering it away from lateral and local bonds; in other words, away from the caste polity. With its excesses curtailed, the remainder of credulity could be arrogated to the transcendently secular state itself via a managed, bureaucratic orthodoxy. In short, the imposture theory was used to evacuate Hinduism of sacerdos and render it a two-storey system fully amenable to the pastoral power of the colonial state (see Chapter 2). Thus bifurcated, it would operate at the level of the individual soul (e.g. Mulji s ethical, reflective Hinduism) and at the level of the population (i.e. legal, ethnological Hinduism), but not in the spaces in between.
The second part of the chapter tries to return to the middle ground of belief the zone of lateral solidarity undermined by the bifurcation of religion into liberal reflection and managed orthodoxy. I call attention to a religious modality that stands in stark contrast to liberal Hinduism (promoted by Mulji), bureaucratic Hinduism (promoted by the state), and sacerdotal Hinduism (the bogey projected by the imposture theory): bhakti. Drawing on Jadunathji s own writings, as well as the work of his Pu()im!rg$ forbearers, I explicate the ethics of radical relationality that, I think, underlies the call for devotional self-surrender (!tm!-nivedan). Against the imposture theory s narrow conception of the guru-disciple bond, I array bhakti s lush taxonomy of devotional affects (bh!vas), arguing that these affects return divinity to the web of human relationships. Enlisting the help of postcolonial theorist Leela Gandhi, I go on to connect this ethics to the Derridean notion of the fiduciary discussed in the Introduction.
By drawing out bhakti s utopian ethics of self-surrender, I do not mean to romanticize the pre-colonial, nor dismiss Mulji s allegations. The gopi morality enjoined by Vallabha does seem to have produced abuses within the Pu()im!rg. Moreover, Mulji was right to use the new discursive position opened by colonialism in order to critique social practices within his community. In doing so, however, he created a double critical conjuncture: just as English education could be used to criticize caste power, bhakti could be used to criticize the political forms of colonialism. The final sections of this chapter attempt to do just this, calling attention to contradictions produced by the conjuncture of bhakti and colonial law. I point to two ways that the juridical discourse of the trial obscured bhakti s fiduciary ethics of radical relationality. I argue that the court split the guru-disciple bond in two to secure the autonomy of the liberal subject. Half of the relationship was handed to the Maharaj s disciples as propositional belief. The other half was returned to the Maharaj himself as his reputation. All that was left to these coldly self-contained parties was the impersonal hierarchy of the d!sya bh!va (the servant s emotion), an affect that Jadunathji could never quite bring himself to endorse.
Although Mulji s critique of the Pu()im!rg was, in part, internal to that tradition, it also, and perhaps more importantly, drew strength from its author s English education (acquired at Elphinstone College). Mulji, like so many of the reformers of his era, articulated his criticism of religion at the interstices of two worlds. Nor was he alone in this. Take for instance the dedication to Mahipatram Rupram s
1877 biography of Mulji, his late friend. First in English, it commends the rising generation who, emancipating themselves from the thraldom of ignorance, superstition, and priestcraft, have dedicated themselves to promote the elevation of their country. Second in Gujarati, it extols those young men who have broken the chains of ignorance and superstition, escaped the net of foolish and wicked gurus, and persevered in promoting their country s progress. [212] There, on consecutive pages, are two analogous concepts: priestcraft and the guru s net (gur+n! j!l). The primary task of this chapter (and the next) will be to measure the distance separating those two terms; its proper focus is neither English nor Gujarati, but rather the blank page space connecting the two.
The series of events that culminated in 1862 s scandalous trial had begun in the previous decade and in a different public arena. The controversy erupted in the Gujarati press, then migrated to the British legal system, and finally attained its canonical proportions in the Anglophone press. It thus demonstrates the degree to which Hindu reformism relied on the points of intersection among different formations of the public in order to promote its agenda.
The first Gujarati newspapers had been founded in the 1820s and 1830s. All of them were managed by Parsis, whose previous involvement in the Anglophone publishing industry lent them requisite professional expertise. In the early years, the Gujarati press busied itself mostly with commercial matters. Not until Dadabhai Naoroji founded the Rast Goftar in 1851 did the Gujarati press take to reform.[213] The Rast Goftar, although run by Parsis and critical of Parsi customs, regularly found fault with Gujarati
Hindus, venturing especially pointed criticisms of the Vallabhac!rya Maharajas. In 1859, for instance, the paper reported on the indecency of Holi celebrations; prostitutes who danced at the temple for a Maharaj s birthday; another Maharaj who hired a dancing Muslim prostitute; and the so-called slave bond (gol!m$ khat) that submitted devotees to the guru s godlike authority).[214] The Rast Goftar took up the question of the Maharaj s purportedly semi-divine status (he was held to be an incarnation of Krishna). It maintains that the Maharajas are merely men (m!*as); by claiming to be avatars of God ($.var), they had turned their followers into servants (c!kr$). The paper describes the Maharajas as tyrannical (julm$), intoxicated (mast!n), and immoral (an$ti), and it denounces their temples as unholy places (apav$tar jag!).[215]
In 1859, when these articles were published, the Rast Goftar had already enlisted the help of an energetic young Hindu, Karsandas Mulji. Since 1855, Mulji had been using the Rast Goftar facilities to publish his own paper, the Satya Prakash. Like so many in the reform party, Mulji had studied at Elphinstone College (described below). In his six years there, he made two friends who would remain his lifelong compatriots in the cause of reform: the poet Narmad!.a#kar L!l.a#kar (Narmad) and the educationalist
Mahipatram Rupram.[216] After graduation, he enlisted Narmad, with his knowledge of Sanskrit and Old Gujarati, to help him study the scriptures of the Vallabhac!rya samprad!ya. Alarmed at their erotic content, Mulji published denunciations of the sect in the Rast Goftar and the Satya Prakash, as well as in handbills and pamphlets. Narmad, meanwhile, lectured against the Maharajas from his home.[217]
The leaders of the samprad!ya soon took note. In mid-1860, Jadunathji Brizratanji Maharaj left his native Surat for Bombay in order to best the reform party in a public debate. He engaged Narmad, and the two publicly wrangled over the topic of widow remarriage; in the process, the poet revealed that he did not accept the shastras as wholly divine. After the debate, the furor continued in the papers. Jadunathji founded the journal Svadharm Vardhak ane Sa*#ay Chedak (Propagator of True Religion and Destroyer of Doubt) in order to compete with Mulji s Satya Prakash. It was during the opening volleys of their paper battle, on 21 October 1860, that Mulji published the article that would land him in court: The Primitive Religion of the Hindus and the Present Heterodox Opinions ( H$nduno asal dharm ne h!ln! p!kha*-$ mato ).[218] October 21 seems otherwise to have been a routine day for the papers. The Rast Goftar published a long lead article on sundry commercial matters and went on to discuss a war in China; the contest between the British and the Russians; the improvement of the police force; caste discrimination; Mumbai, Karachi, Calcutta; income taxes; coffee and opium; and the English failings. [219] None of these, however, would prove as significant as Mulji s diatribe.
Mulji s basic argument was that because scriptures like the Puranas and Shastras state that the Kali Yug will proliferate false religions, the Pu()im!rg, which originated in the Kali Yug, must be false (kho)!) and heterodox (p!kha*-$). Mulji enjoins a return to the purity of primitive (asal) Hinduism, whether Vedic or classical. He fulminates against the Maharajas for their misdeeds, and he specifies that Jadunathji had behaved nefariously with his female followers. He claims that the sect instructs male devotees to surrender their body, mind, and wealth (tan, man, and dhan) to the guru before enjoying them themselves and much more scandalously that wealth has been generally interpreted to include women. Some of the article s acridity gets lost in translation.[220] Its basic allegation, however, is more than clear: the Maharajas stand convicted by Mulji of imposture ()hag!$). As he puts it, there can be no greater heresy or deceit than this, to blind people and throw dust into their eyes. [221]
It would be some time before the Maharaj sued Mulji for libel, and the reasons why he did so will be discussed below. In short, it seemed like the traditional caste leadership was unable to manage Mulji, and so Jadunathji turned to the ascendant British power. When the libel suit came to court in January 1862, most Bania and
Bhattia caste leaders sided with the plaintiff, the Maharaj. Only two shets stood with Karsandas: Mangaldas Nathubhai of the Banias and Lakhmidas Khimji of the Bhattias, both of whom were sympathetic to the reform agenda. The rest, including Gopaldas Madhavdas, the head of the Bania Mahajan, stood with the Maharaj. In total, there were thirty-one witnesses for the plaintiff and thirty-three for the defense. Both Gopaldas Madhavdas and his brother Varjivandas testified on behalf of Jadunathji, as did a number of relatively non-influential Bania and Bhattia merchants. Defense witnesses included Lakhmidas Khimji, Mangaldas Nathubhai, Dr. John Wilson, and leading Elphinstonians like Narmad and Dr. Bhau Daji. Their lurid accounts of the guru s sexual escapades, culminating in Daji s attestation to the Maharaj s struggle with syphilis, won the case for the defense Arguing for the plaintiff were Mr. Bayley and Mr. Scoble.
Arguing for the defendents were Mr. Anstey and Mr. Dunbar. Chief Justice Mathew
Sausse presided over the trial, assisted by Justice Joseph Arnould.[222]
Extensive coverage in the two major Bombay dailies guaranteed the case its national notoriety. Competition between the Bombay Gazette and the Times of India shaped the development of both papers after the 1861 amalgamation of the latter from the Bombay Times, the Bombay Standard, and the Telegraph and Courier (see Chapter 2). Both papers doubtless hoped that the Maharaj Libel Case s irresistible admixture of salacious sex and reformist virtue would help sell copy. Sales and circulation are at this point, of course, impossible to gauge. What is clear, however, is that other newspapers took note of the Bombay dailies extended fascination with the case; both came to be identified with it by other voices in the Anglo-Indian press. For instance, the Poona Observer, never shy in its opinions, openly disapproved of the entire affair. The Maharaj Libel case, it wrote shortly after the commencement of the trial, is dragging its dirty length along in the Supreme Court of Bombay. The case is about as disgusting [a] one as can be imagined. [223] Two weeks later, the Observer complained that the Maharaj s libel case still draws its slow and filthy length along in the Supreme Court, to the great disgust of all the respectable readers of the two Bombay dailies, the columns of which are occupied, to the exclusion of better matter, by the disgraceful revelations of the abominations of which the Maharaj is accused. The paper conceded the importance of the trial, and with characteristically racist invective, waxed aghast at how a heathen is not to be trusted because despite his polite and liberal appearance in public, at home he remains an abject slave of a superstition that exceeds the bounds of even the filthiest imagination. The reactionary Observer used the case to argue against the tolerance advocated by the Times of India.[224] Nine days later, the Observer reported that the Times had decided to stop publishing about the case; but, more than two weeks after this, it was still chiding the Times for having
worked its way into a state of religious frenzy about this wretched libel case. [225]
The English-language papers were quick to insinuate the case into the global history of priestcraft. As early as December 1861, during the trial of the Bhattia Conpiracy Case, the Bombay Gazette identified the trial as a most suggestive and instructive chapter in the history of superstition; and also a most revolting one. Comparing the Maharajas principle of apostolical succession to the papacy, the paper laments that they would give out that they are incarnations of God and yet persist in the most loathsome filth of sensuality. Their exposure should result in making them ashamed of their creed and life. Shame, the Gazette suggests, is what separates the European from the native. [226] The Poona Observer likewise compared the Maharajas to the Popes, going on to equate their followers with the credulous Mormons, and even trotting out a topical couplet from John Dryden ( In pious times ere priestcraft did begin/ Before polygamy was made a sin ).[227] In a decidedly unholy vein, the Times of India compared the Maharaj to Satan, the Prince of Darkness, who had held India s millions in the bonds of superstition as his miserable tools. [228]
Upon the conclusion of the trial, the papers celebrated the exposure of the Maharaj and anticipated the decline of sacerdotal religion. On May 2, the Bombay Gazette observed that the dark powers that tyrannize over the human mind may be seen in every age of the world. Just as the priesthood in the dark ages had subordinated others to their authority as though they were a superior rank of mortals, now the mighty mass of mind in India [is held] under the power of the Brahmins. The Maharaj Libel Case has begun to undo this bondage by subjecting spiritual tyranny to investigation and dissent. [229] The next day, the Times of India asked whether it was possible that Jadunathji Brizrattanji would be able to maintain his position as a sanctified teacher, as an incarnation of God after the public revelation and exposure of his real character. It praised the Satya Prakash for having verified its name :
Through a long night of superstition and darkness, vile creatures like this Maharaj have been able to make their dens of vice and debauchery seem to their spell-bound followers to be the holy temples of God. But as soon as the morning light comes, the place is found in full corruption and uncleanness; magical spells lose all effect; and all men of a better sort rise disgusted, and at any cost break loose from such a haunt.[230]
Disenchantment was the order of the day, and Mulji s vindication seemed a harbinger of a Hindu enlightenment on the verge of dawning.
As coverage of the trial s conclusion spread, the trope of the press as spellbreaking force of enlightenment spread with it. Calcutta s Friend of India hailed public opinion through the press as the lone instrument by which such practices as those of the Wallabhacharyas can alone be exposed. [231]Meanwhile, Bombay s bilingual Dnyanodaya likewise claimed that the affair serves more than anything else to reveal the abominations of Hindooism and the direct results of its doctrines upon the lives of its votaries (both papers were run by Christian missionaries).[232] The conservative Bombay Saturday Review declared the court s ruling the first legal vindication of the great principle of religious liberty in India, and the heaviest blow ever to the system of caste. [233] Press clippings like these would later attain greater permanence in Mulji s History of the Sect of Maharajas (1865). The book took the form of an Orientalist monograph, which included an abridged transcript of the trial and a sampling of the press coverage as an appendix. The History, like the affair as a whole, demonstrates the complex affinities and affiliations among philological scholarship, English education, Hindu reform, Christian missions, the colonial state, and the vernacular and English press.
As the trial unfolded, the Gujarati press also continued its coverage of the affair.
For instance, a February Rast Goftar and Satya Prakash article on The Gist of the Libel Case, reports the major developments of the trial in its first month. The article reiterates the primary accusations made during the trial: (a) that many devotees take their gurus to be avatars of God or Krishna ($.var athav! kar.an), and (b) that these devotees submit their body, mind, and wealth to their guru-god; not to do so, the article alleges, is thought to be a sin (p!p). The devotee (sevak) rocks the Maharaj in a swing (hi*-ol!), just as the Maharaj rocks the deity. The article further repeats the slanders made of the Maharaj in court: he salaciously splashes red dye (gul!l) on the chests of Pu()im!rg$ women; he has his devotees drink dirty water (melun paaNi) in
which he washed his feet and dhoti; he gives out his chewed p!n as pras!dam; he solicits worshipful leg massages; he forced the community into a slavery bond. The article ultimately affirms that the Pu()im!rg$ sect (panth) is the opposite of the original
(asal) Hindu dharma.[234]
As the trial dragged on, further articles used its notoriety to lodge criticisms against other allegedly immoral practices like Holi.[235] By the conclusion of the case in late April, the Satya Prakash could proudly proclaim itself satisfied (sa#to.) with all its hard work (mehanat). Today s victory (fateh) is not ours, the paper wrote, but belongs to truth; they thank God ($.var) and attribute the victory to him. The scandal, it seems, was meant merely as form of devotional service (upak!r$).[236] A few weeks later, a followup article noted that much had already been said on the immoral (an$t$) subject of the maharajas, and suggested that perhaps there was nothing left to say. [237]
The Maharaj Libel Case resonated widely due to its lurid dramatization of the discourse of priestly imposture, which throughout the nineteenth century had organized British depictions of Hinduism. The Case served in a sense as a point of application for the imposture theory of religion: the presuppositions of press and court derived from the priestcraft narrative, and both public bodies sought to right the wrongs implied by the trope of charlatanic deception. They sought, that is, to replace Hindu hierarchy with an egalitarian social order consistent both with liberal political theory and with the governmental exigencies of colonial rule. In many ways, what is most notable about the case is the apparent inevitability of its outcome. This morality play about a nefarious guru was, I submit, pre-scripted. The trial was overdetermined by intersecting discourses that allowed it to emerge as a news story and that constrained that story s possible endings. Later on in this chapter, I will attempt to read this tale against the grain. First, however, I will situate it within its broader political and cultural context a context in which the line between the political and the
cultural was very much a point of contestation.
It is not a question of theology that has been before us! It is a question of morality. [238] Judge Joseph Arnould s proclamation resounded through the packed chambers of the Bombay High Court. Journalists scribbled frantically as the judge explained that
what is morally wrong cannot be theologically right that when practices which say the very foundation of morality, which involve a violation of the eternal and immutable laws of Right are established in the name and under the sanction of
Religion, they ought, for the common welfare of Society, and in the interest of Humanity itself to be publicly denounced and exposed. (MLC, 480)
Arnould s judgment relied on a very secular logic. Arched above the particularities of the world s religions, there stands a single immutable law, inscribed in nature and preserved by the state. This state, through its appeal to moral philosophy, stakes its claim to a position of universality from which it can arbitrate among the competing claims of the many religious laws and communities that populate its territories. Such a position had an obvious and enduring appeal for the British colonial state in India, never more urgently than in the early 1860s, as the state reframed its rule after the 1857 Uprisings. By claiming to stand above religions, the British state also produced itself as standing above Indians, a colonized population reduced to the religious identities by which they were ruled.
In the following discussion, I will parse Arnould s claim. First, I suggest that Karsandas Mulji s article operated in the mode of oppositional heterodoxy: his dissent was voiced from within Vallabhac!rya tradition as much as from without. I then explore how British state used such heterodox to assert its sovereignty over Hindu caste polities. My general argument throughout this section is that colonial governmentality rendered Hindu theology an object of managerial control. It used the powers of publicity to sever the lateral bonds that constituted caste groups, in order both to convene an undifferentiated secular public and to produce a properly bureaucratic Hinduism.
As Gauri Viswanathan has suggested, oppositional heterodoxy serves many of the functions as secularism: it articulates a space outside of religious orthodoxy from which that orthodoxy can be criticized. Oppositional heterodoxy amplifies contradictions internal to received tradition in order to articulate its critique of hegemonic social forms.[239] This breed of heterodox critique is, I will suggest, precisely what Mulji attempted in his libelous article. Mulji referred to the Pur!*as and "!stras in order to make his claim that because the Vallabhac!ri panth was created (c!lu thayo)
long after the commencement of the Kali Yug, it must by definition be a fake religion.
Like generations of traditionalist critics before him, Mulji bases his argument on scriptural authority (hindu .!stran! vacan pram!*e).[240] Indeed, Vallabhac!rya himself had used the concept of the Kali Yug to, in effect, criticize the Vedas. As he insisted, although the Vedas might have been a suitable basis for devotion in before the carnage of Kur+k(etra, only bhakti can save corrupt modern humanity. Abstruse Vedic verses hardly even make sense in these dark times.
Mulji inverts this argument: bhakti is to blame for humanity s debased state. Drawing on his Elphinstone education, Mulji articulated an Enlightenment Hinduism predicated on a reformed humanity; but, as he framed it, Vedic revival was the key to reform. In order to redeem the modern age, the Vedas and Shastras must displace the gurus and their theology of love. Mulji thus attempted return Hinduism to Vedic orthodoxy. His orthodoxy, however, was functionally heterodox: that is, espoused from within the Pu()im!rg, it departed from and criticized the devotional norms of his community. Mulji astutely triangulated three vectors of critical thought: English Enlightenment, Vallabhac!ryan bhakti, and neo-Vedic orthodoxy. Their convergence can be seen in one crucial concept that anchors much of Mulji s corpus: uddh!r, or emancipation. In Pu()im!rg$ theology, uddh!r referred to the subsumption of the soul into Krishna. For Mulji, it retains this sense while also indicating social reform.[241]
Mulji s emancipation is thus positioned between traditions; through it, Enlightenment and bhakti each come to inflect the other, rendering tradition of whatever variety strange unto itself.
Mulji gave voice to an oppositional heterodoxy; Arnould, in the passage quoted above, used heterodoxy as an excuse for the extension of state power. Precisely because religious publics proliferate dissenting counter-publics, the state assumes the role of managing dissent. In the Bombay of the early 1860s, the legal management of heterodoxy often allowed the colonial state to intervene within what historian Amrita Shodhan has termed caste polities. Shodhan argues that between the 1850s and the 1870s, the Bombay castes stopped functioning as little publics and started to function as sociological descriptors borne by individuals situated within a non-differentiated public, defined by the centrality of the British state.[242] Mulji s career demonstrates the shift: in the 1850s he took the caste polity as his primary public arena, but this was no longer possible in the same way by the 1870s. Caste had become anachronistic identity within the non-differentiated public; it had become the object, not the locus, of reform.[243]
The Maharaj Libel Case exemplifies this process. The Maharaj s followers hailed from the Bania and Bhattia castes, two of the wealthiest merchant communities in Bombay. Each caste was divided into several sub-castes (like Mulji s Kapol Bania caste), and each of these was presided over by a shet. The several shets of each caste met periodically to discuss matters pertinent to the caste as a whole. This body of all the shets was termed the Mahajan. Caste leadership traditionally had the power to excommunicate members, but recent regulations imposed by the British had constrained their ability to do so. Because of these regulations, if caste leaders were to excommunicate a member, they would run a serious risk of incurring a lawsuit. The Maharajas in particular did not want to defile themselves by court appearances, or to admit subordination to the British state; so, in January 1859, they circulated a caste contract that pledged its signatories both to support the excommunication of dissenters and to help keep the Maharajas out of court. Captained by the Kapol Bania shet, Varjivandas Madhavdas, most of the city s Bania and Bhatia leaders signed the contract which, on January 23, Mulji excoriated in an article titled The Slavery Bond (gol!m$ khat).[244] These events were replayed two and a half years later, in the build-up to the Maharaj Libel Case. On September 6, 1861, two thousand Bhattias met to resolve that whoever sided with Mulji by testifying against the Maharaj in court would be excommunicated. Mulji got wind of the meeting and charged its leaders with conspiracy. The Bhattia Conspiracy Case was heard in December 1861, a preamble to the Maharaj Libel Case proper. The leading conspirators were fined for obstructing justice. By criminalizing the Bhatia alliance as a conspiracy, the court implied that the state alone, and not civil bodies, possesses the authority to protect the rights of its subjects. In other words, the caste was not permitted to govern itself.[245]
As Christine Dobbin has argued, the rift in Gujarati caste polities predated the 1850s. Two class fractions the English-educated intelligentsia and the traditional elites competed for hegemony among Bombay s Gujarati Hindus, and it was this competition that drove the controversy that landed the Maharaj in court. As Dobbin demonstrates, the new Bombay intelligentsia used its English education to claim power away from traditional caste elites. Religion emerged as a prime site of contestation for these two groups: religious leaders authority was often intimately linked to that of the caste shets; thus, by bringing down a priest, a reformer might also bring down his secular counterpart.
The intelligentsia had gotten their degrees from Elphinstone College, which was founded in 1834 to spread English learning among the colonized; the curriculum featured instruction in courses in literature, history, natural science, and political economy. [246] Books circulating at the college included not only literary titles (Milton s
Poems, Robinson Crusoe, the Arabian Nights) and histories (Thomas Macaulay s History of
England, Edward Gibbon s Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, James Mill s History of
British India), but also works on political economy (David Ricardo, John Stuart Mill,
Thomas Malthus), utilitarianism (e.g. Jeremy Bentham s Principles of Morals and
Legislation), epistemology (John Locke s On the Conduct of the Understanding, Thomas Reid s Philosophy of the Human Mind), and natural theology (William Paley), as well as books by French thinkers like Pascal and Montesquieu. Some of these works were also distilled in primers like Easy Lessons on Reasoning and, in Gujarati, A Youth s Book on Natural Theology.[247] Elphinstone students were encouraged to criticize the social ills of
India, and several won prizes for their essays on choice reformist topics like infanticide. In his prize-winning essay, for instance, the young Bhau Daji extolled those dignified, rational, and active beings who had devoted themselves to dispelling the darkness, which covers the rest of our countrymen. [248]
The disruption of Gujarati caste polities thus had its roots in British imperialism, but via an imperial organ other than the Bombay High Court. As discussed in the previous chapter (Chapter 2), the political logic of reform in colonial India was complex. As I suggested, drawing on work by Nicholas Dirks and Michel Foucault, the nineteenth century witnessed a shift in the form of imperial power. Where once it had concerned itself primarily with statecraft, it increasingly came to reframe its mission as an intervention in the field of priestcraft; that is, the colonial state extended the reach of its power by trying to redeem Indian souls and liberate the colonized from the unjust rule of religious leaders. As Leela Gandhi reminds us, the Utilitarian discourse of improvement was caught up with the gospel of governmentality as a civilizing mission. [249] The political logic of reform assumed a diffuse field of power, concerned with social practices and individual subjectivation. In place of fearfully submissive devotional subjects, proudly autonomous rational subjects would come to pervade the subcontinent, remaking its religious multitudes as rational publics. In Chapter 2, I analyzed this mode of pastoral power with primary reference to Christian missionaries. Here, my focus is on Hindu reformers.
The agendas of men like Mulji and Daji were not the same as the agendas of the imperial state; however, as the Maharaj Libel Case demonstrates, these two parties did enter into strategic alliance. The Bombay Gazette wrote that the case had served to vindicate the liberty of the press, the justice of English law, the cause of progress in this land, and more especially the moral reform which is struggling to make headway in this community against the most powerfully antagonistic influences. [250] As this comment suggests, the Maharaj Libel Case also demonstrated the mutual determination of these four fields: the free press, English law, progress, and moral reform. For example, both the state and the press undercut caste polities claims to sovereignty by using the rhetoric of publicity (cf. Chapter 2). In Judge Arnould s concluding remarks, he spoke at great length about the importance of the press in opening Hindu society. Arnould congratulated Mulji and friends for fulfilling their journalistic duty.[251] By his account, the legal outcome of the trial seems secondary to its use as a vehicle of publicity. Although the trial has been spoken of as having involved a great waste of the public time, Arnould disagrees. That the case was discussed thus openly before a population so intelligent as that of the natives of Western India, is to be applauded: it must have taught many to think; it must have led many to enquire (MLC, 479-80). A public journalist, he wrote, is a public teacher; the true function of the press, that by virtue of which it has rightly grown to be one of the great powers of the modern world is the function of teaching, elevating and enlightening those who fall within the range of its influence. The press must expose and denounce evil and barbarous practices; to attack usages and customs inconsistent with moral purity and social progress. The press has the ability to change and purify the public opinion which is the real basis on which these evils are built and the real power by which they are perpetuated (MLC, 423). For this reason, the the liberty of the press should be placed upon an inaccessible height (379). As is clear from Arnould s remarks, the state served as the guarantor of the free press and did so eagerly insofar as both were involved in parallel projects of social reform.
Arnould s comments bear comparison with a juridical defense of the press with a far more insidious ring. In 1853, Justice Erskine Perry observed that
in courts of justice the veil which shrouds the privacy of Oriental life is necessarily drawn aside, the strong ties which at other times bind together caste and family in pursuit of a common object are loosened under the pressure of stronger individual interests, and there, amidst masses of conflicting testimony, and with subtler intellects to deal with than usually appear before European tribunals, the motives, reasonings, and actions of the native population of India are displayed in broad light and may be traced with inestimable advantage.[252]
Perry attributes several powers to publicity. First, it allows the court to assert its
authority over domestic life and therefore undermine the sphere of spiritual sovereignty claimed by the colonized. Second, it scrambles familial solidarity, temporarily severing domestic bonds by hailing subjects individually, their interests piqued by structures of legal responsibility. Third, it brings the natives into view as a population, a collective body to be mapped and managed by the ethnological apparatus of the state. Thus, the act of exposure reinforces the political logic of governmentality: it apprehends the governed as population and as individuals, eroding forms of solidarity that might run counter to the imperatives of pastoral power. I will have more to say about those lines of solidarity below. First, however, I mean to close this discussion by calling attention to the form of religion that the secular state actually promoted.
The colonial state did not do away with religion entirely, however. Instead, it bureaucratized it. In Foucault s terms, religion would no longer just be used to manage the soul; it would be used to manage the population. The general effort of the British was to replace irrational, irregular, local religious practices with sets of religious rules and regulations that could be absorbed by the administrative apparatus of the state. To be sure, administrative religion had featured significantly in Indian political life well before the coming of the British. But as the Maharaj Libel Case so aptly demonstrates, the post-1857 ethnographic state consolidated and extended this modality of power in an unprecedented manner and, in the process, effected major changes within Hinduism itself.
In the Maharaj Libel Case, the imposture theory of religion was used to narrate a shift from charismatic Hinduism to bureaucratic Hinduism, from the affective intensities of bhakti to the calmly reflective liberal faith of Karsandas Mulji. Indeed it seems to suggest that the two major modalities of reformed Hinduism (that is, liberal-reflective and legal-bureaucratic) were mutually reinforcing, both working in tandem to suppresses the alleged excesses of devotional self-surrender and spiritual eroticism. Part of what was at stake in the Maharaj Libel Affair was what Max Weber has called the routinization of charisma. During the trial, the guru would be leached of his godlike aura. This shift was most apparent in the discussion of which text enjoined faith in the guru; it was presumed that the Maharaj s sacred authority inhered not in his person, nor in Krishna, but rather in the scriptural canon (MLC, 193-196, 238).
Textual fastidiousness did not, of course, originate with the British. Jadunathji himself had established belief in the .!stras as a major point of dissension between the orthodox and reform parties; in his public debate with Narmad, for instance, he demanded of the poet whether he held the .!stras to be divinely created ($.vark/t).[253] The poet did not, but the guru made it very clear that their divinity was a central tenet of his orthodoxy: the .!stra-sayer is God himself (.!stra kahen!r $.var che), and those who claim that the .!stras are the sayings of man (manu(ya) are ignorant (agy!n$); they abandon the .!stra-sect (.!strano mat) for whatever authority pleases them (pot!n$ marj$ pram!*e).[254]
Hindu texts did, however, assume new functions as they entered the purview of the colonial state. It is now a scholarly commonplace that Hinduism is an invention of the colonial period, and the Maharaj Libel Case is exemplary of the shifts wrought within South Asian religion by Orientalism and reformism.[255] J rgen L tt identified the trial as a fulcrum in the epochal shift from erotic to martial Hinduism, from Krishna-lila to Ram-rajya.[256] David Haberman used the case to illustrate the imperial complicity of textualist Orientalism with the colonial courts.[257] It seems that, during the Maharaj Libel Case, an erotic Hinduism predicated on the micro-politics of the caste polity was replaced by a chastely impersonal Hinduism predicated on managerial expertise of the state-sponsored Orientalist.
The Maharaj Libel Case put the Bombay High Court in the peculiar position of having to adjudicate Hindu orthodoxy a peculiarity that was not lost on the court itself, which spent a good portion of the demurrer hearing debating whether such adjudication was legally appropriate.[258] To adjudge orthodoxy seemed to compromise the secularist constraints placed upon the state by the principle of non-interference in religion. The court also worried about the feasibility of trying orthodoxy, when the judges lacked professional expertise in Hindu scriptural traditions. Although prosecuting attorney Bayley argued that the case be admitted because it breaches of the moral law and could thus be tried without reference to doctrine, Chief Justice Sausse concluded that the nature of orthodoxy was very much was confronted the court. Following the terms set forth in the alleged libel, they would determine heterodoxy by comparing Hindu practice to the regulations detailed in Hindu
Shastras (MLC, 37).
As early as 1846, H. H. Wilson had noted that Vallabha preached that privation formed no part of sanctity, and that it was the duty of the teachers and his disciples to worship their Deity, not in nudity and hunger, but in costly apparel and choice food; not in solitude and mortification, but in the pleasures of society, and the enjoyment of this world. [259][260] The Orientalist sense that the Pu()im!rg was a sort of Hindu
Epicureanism was reinforced by the Maharaj Libel Case, which, through the testimony of missionary-Orientalist Rev. John Wilson, incorporated H. H. Wilson s expertise. Later, this understanding of the Pu()im!rg would be made even more canonical by Monier Monier-Williams, who expressed horror at the sensuous, gender bending of the Pu()im!rg.[261] Karsandas Mulji also made a foray into the genre of the Orientalist monograph, with his A History of the Sect of Maharajas (1865).
It was through Orientalist texts like these that orthodox Hinduism came into
view as an entity that could be managed by the courts. As I have suggested in this section, the Maharaj Libel Case put the Bombay High Court forward as the caretaker of secular morality ; in the name of this universal code, it came to intervene within religion and within caste polities closely associated with religion. As the locus of political life moved from the caste to the undifferentiated public, the Maharaj s charisma was routinized. Authentic Hinduism was no longer to be invested in sacred persons, but rather in sacred texts overseen by the Orientalist state bureaucracy.
Reflective ethics would govern the individual, and bureaucratic religion the population.
I now turn to the social order that this arrangement sought to replace. As I will explain,
Mulji s individualistic Hinduism was pitted against a radical ethics of self-surrender.
In his N(ti-vacan (Discourses on Ethics) (1859), a collection of sixty-five previously published articles, Karsandas Mulji offered his thoughts on sundry topics, some familial (woman, father, son), some emotional (anger, joy, sorrow), some religious (e.g. Real
Religion and the Real Path [ kharo dharm tath! kharo m!rg ], Devotion to God and Ethics [ $.var-bhakti ane n$ti ]).[262] The collection opens with a meditation on the nature of God. As Mulji insists, God is one (ekaj che) and is not bound to any particular caste (te j!te $.var nath$). He stands at a firm remove from this world, eschewing avatars, aloft on his heavenly throne (takht). From on high He shines light (prak!sh) on all the world and, in the process, gives life to all beings. Mulji enjoins his reader to worship, praise, and love (p+j!, stuti, ane bhakti kar) this God, the maker of the world, the most powerful, the all-knowing.[263]
Here as elsewhere, Mulji proffers a disenchanted Hinduism that ensures its rationality by carefully divorcing divinity from the empirical world, lodging it instead an ethereal arena of impersonal ethical precepts. As Mahipatram Rupram put it, Mulji tried to destroy the rotten, immoral system called Pushti Marga and replace it with a more rational form of worship. [264] By eliminating the allegedly arbitrary powers of hereditary god-men. Mulji sought to sever one potent point of physical contact between the immanent and the transcendent.
While Mulji is careful to include bhakti on his list of prescribed devotional forms, he effectively subordinates it to praise and worship, constraining its more capacious semantic range within the hierarchy implied by both those terms. To invoke a phrase elucidated below, Mulji reduces bhakti to the d!sya bh!va, the servile affect that a subject feels for his king or a servant for his master. While the bhakti of hierarchical abasement was the bhakti on trial at the Bombay High Court in 1862, it was not the only kind of devotion enjoined by Sri Vallabhac!rya and his descendents. Jadunathji once complained of those who delimit bhakti s rich panoply of devotional forms with the stale singularity of the divine father. Fools, he wrote, think that God can only be worshipped as a son respects his father; all emotions are divine, as are both genders.[265] Devotional praxis should reflect the innate multiplicity of human affects and human relations. In what follows, I will attempt to recuperate the ethics of radical relationality that, I think, undergirds Jadunath s claim.
According to postcolonial theorist Leela Gandhi, Immanuel Kant founded the
radical freedom of the ethical agent-subject on a critical refusal of religion. The Kantian subject was singular, self-identical, self-sufficient, immune, and transcendental, and in order to be all of these things, it had to secure the boundary separating its confident ipseity from divine alterity. As Gandhi puts it, religion threatened the liberal subject with hybridity that is, with a messy admixture of self and other, of the empirical and the transcendent.[266] Drawing on Derrida s notion of the fiduciary, Gandhi suggests that where Kant s reflective faith resisted subjective disjunction, dogmatic faith triggers an interruptive unraveling of the self by opening it to the unwavering demand of the other. As Gandhi explains, faith that refuses to close itself off into a totality by remaining open to the unknown is the ether of the address and relation of the utterly other. [267] By traversing the limits of the liberal subject, such faith discloses in place of a separated and disenchanted world, a concatenated multiverse, strung together in a horizontal web of relations. [268]
If we follow this utopian gloss on theistic devotion, the following rule emerges. It is precisely in its ability to promote hybridity that is, to blur the boundary between the otherworldly and the empirical, between self and other that religion offers its greatest challenge to liberal subjectivity and the political forms predicated upon it. It is by diffusing divinity into the horizontal web of human relations that faith founds ethics. By Gandhi s account, both prayer and desire turn the self ever outward in an anxious address of an other that precedes, orients, and undermines it. As I will suggest, Gandhi s account of religion helps us clarify the ethical stakes of the bhakti devotionalism convicted of immorality by Mulji and the Bombay High Court.
As N. A. Thoothi defined it in the 1920s, bhakti means prayer, devotion, worship, adoration. It presupposes complete self-surrender, surrender of the mind, body, and spirit of the devotee to the object of his worship, viz. God. It refers to the longings of the throbbing human heart which strives to be in tune with the love and will of God. [269] That is to say that bhakti uses prayer to cultivate an intense desire for the divine other, and this desire is meant to rupture the sovereign subject. Love does not remain a singular affect in the major treatises on bhakti; rather, bhakti s explicators have detailed a lush taxonomy of emotions that repeatedly returns devotion to the mundane arena of human relationships.
In his journal, the Propagator of True Religion and Destroyer of Doubt, Jadunathji specified nine modes of devotion (navadh! bhakti) central to Pu()im!rg$ tradition: .rava*, or hearing the praises of the deity; k$rtan, or devotional singing; smara*, or remembering the deity at all times; p!dsevan, worshipping the holy feet of the svar+p or image of Sri Krishna; arcan, worship of the deity[270]; vandan, praising the deity; d!sya, or servility; sakhya, or friendliness; and finally !tm!nivedan, or self-surrender.[271] This list suggests a progressive work upon the self. Devotion begins with establishing habitual practices (hearing, singing, remembering); proceeds by extending these practices into pervasive attitudes (servility, friendliness); and culminates in the complete loss or surrender of the self. The askesis of bhakti thus interrupts the selfidentical subject by reorienting daily life toward divine alterity.
Jadunathji s teachings derive, of course, from the writings of Vallabhac!rya
(1479-1531). Vallabha was born in modern Andhra Pradesh to a Telugu brahman named Lakshman Bhatt. During his life, he toured the subcontinent three times and earned many accolades, including the title acharya after winning a public debate (#"str"rth) at the court of Vijayanagara. Through most of his adult life, Vallabha s worked primarily in the north, spending considerable time in both Braj and Banaras. He is now considered one of the major expositors of early modern bhakti. His major teachings are outlined in commentaries on the Brahma Sutras and Bhagavad Purana, as well as in sixteen shorter treatises (the Sodasagranthas); his followers have further expanded the literature of the sect (the Vallabhac!rya sampradaya, or Pu()im!rg) in Sanskrit, Braj
Bhasa, Gujarati, and Hindi. In addition to delineating of a pure non-dualist metaphysics (see below), Vallabha also insisted that the major Krishnaite text, the Bhagavad Purana, be included with the trio of scriptures that served as the foundation for orthodox philosophical debate (Brahma-Sutras, Upanisads, Bhagavad-Gita).
bhaktim"rg, the path of devotion. Unlike yogic and philosophical forms of religious practices, it taught that liberation from this world could only occur through the grace (pu%+i or anugraha) of God, and not through the efforts of the human soul. During his life, Vallabha personally initiated eighty-four followers into the Pu()im!rg. The most famous of these was surely the poet S+rd!s, whose lyrics are still recited throughout North India.[272] Vallabha organized his sect around his family. In a notable departure from the renunciatory norms of Vai(*ava orthodoxy, Vallabha decided to marry. He had two sons, Gopin!th and Vi))haln!th. The latter proved the more capable leader, and it is his seven sons whose descendents still structure the samprad!ya. One of these sons, Yadunatha, moved with his svarupa of Krishna to Surat; the Jadunathji libeled by
Mulji would have been his descendent.[273]
Jadunath s typology of the navadh" bhakti was common during Vallabha s era.
An influential articulation, for instance, is to be found in the writings of R+pa Gosv!mi (d. 1555), a follower of Vallabha s contemporary K/(*a Caitanya. Rupa Gosvami writes that as both sakhya and !tm!-nivedana are very rare and difficult, it is only a very few deserving and qualified persons with ever deepening faith that are found to possess them as a result of their spiritual practices. The ecstasy of self-surrender, when it comes at all, comes as the endpoint to devotional praxis. Vallabha, as Richard Barz explains, inverted this arrangement by making self-surrender the prerequisite to the other eight modes of devotion. In the Pu()im!rg, the young aspirant commits himself to Krishna by reciting the mantra Sri Krishan is my refuge (.r$ k/(*a0 .ara*am mama), and it is only after surrendering himself that he begins to practice the navadh! bhakti.[274] By placing self-surrender first, Vallabha minimized the agency of the devotee. Unlike religious disciplines in which aspirants accrue spiritual power through their own assiduous efforts, in the Pu()im!rg, action follows from and is the sign of God s grace (anugraha or pu()i).[275]
In an additional departure from the norms of renunciation, Vallabha married and encouraged his followers to do the same. Although the place of women and family life in writings of the sect remained fraught, Vallabha s decision to discourage full renunciation seems to have stemmed from a belief in the virtues of human interdependence. As he put it, [i]t is not necessary to take the vow of sanny!sa (worldrenunciation) in order to practice the nine-fold bhakti, for in the practice of that bhakti the help of other bhaktas is essential; both the pride common to the state of sanny!sa and the duties of the state of sanny!sa are contrary to the bhaktim!rga. [276] To be sure, the ultimate thrust of bhakti is to turn the devotee away from his family and toward Krishna, from the world (laukika) to the otherworldly (alaukika). The more that Krishna comes to serve as the ideal locus of all love, of whichever type, the less love remains for daily life. Vallabha even went so far as to claim that familial relations entangle the soul in delusions. [277] To break with Maya is to break with the family and with all worldly relationships. The paradox of bhakti devotion, however, is that it is precisely the intensity of emotion generated by these relationships that is the surest means of world-transcendence. In order to lose the world, you first have to receive it.
Pu()im!rg$ praxis promotes five devotional affects, the bhaktibh!vas common to many bhakti sects. In d!sya bh!va, the devotee approaches Krishna as a servant to a master; in sakhya bh!va, as friend to friend; in v!tsalya bh!va, as parent to child; in madhura bh!va, as a gopi, one of the female cowherds who cavorted with the amorous youthful Krishna in the fields of Braj; and, finally, in sh!nta bh!va, in complete tranquility. Vallabha did not favor this latter affect because his bhakti was, in Barz s words, based on the strong emotional ties already present in human beings. [278] For similar reasons, the austere d!sya bh!va with its regal formalities likewise lacks his full endorsement. The most intimate affects are the most likely to launch the devotee into all-consuming love for Krishna. The friendly egalitarianism of the sakhya bh!va, while at the apex of the affective hierarchy, is generally reserved for luminaries like the poet
Surdas. More common are parental tenderness (v!tsalya bh!va) and romantic love
(madhura bh!va).
The tender attachments cultivated by the sect are demonstrated by its daily regimen of service (sev!) to the deity. The Pu()im!rg$s distance themselves from the worshipful formalism they view as common in South Asian religions. For the Pu()im!rg, the statue of Krishna is not a m+rti, or representation of the deity; it is his svar+p, or actual living form. The structure housing Krishna s svar+p is not a temple (mandir), it is his mansion home (havel$). The act of devotion is not worship (p+j!); it is loving service (sev!). Early in the morning, devotees awaken Krishna and leave him a light breakfast. A little later they dress him for the day, making sure to suit his clothes to the season. After this, the devotees present him with a full lunchtime feast, put him down for a nap, rouse him again for a light lunch, offer him an evening meal accompanied by honorific lamp lighting, and then put him to bed with a snack in case he gets hungry.[279] While the devotees might act in part as servants, this ceremony in its overall tenor seems to position Krishna as a child who needs the tender attention of loving parents (i.e. the v!tsalya bh!va).
If the Pu()im!rg teaches devotees to find God in the world, this makes good metaphysical sense. Vallabha was a strict non-dualist, and he wrote at length about the ultimate unity of God and world. Ved!nta, one of the six orthodox (!stika) schools of classical Indian philosophy (saddar.ana) had long pondered the relationship of the visible world and the divine. Non-dualist (advaita) thinkers maintained that there was no difference between the two. All entities in the physical world are part of a single ontological ground, known as Brahman. It is due to ignorance that humans perceive difference where none exists in reality. Devotional praxis is meant to liberate the soul by revealing the world to be an illusion. The ninth century philosopher "a#kar!c!rya produced the most influential articulation of the advaita position, and it was Shankara s metaphysical system that Vallabha sought to revise. Briefly, Shankara posited M!y!, a discrete agent of illusion, to account for the emergence of the physical world from selfsufficient Brahman. Although the physical world cannot properly be said to exist, that it even seems to do so is an illusion produced by Maya. In Shankara s thought, the ontological status of Maya remains ambiguous. He maintains that Maya is both real and unreal (it is real as long as illusion lasts, but has no existence apart from Brahman); but the nuance of his apophasis has often been lost on later commentators. To many, Shankara seemed to grant Maya a status on par with Brahman: eternal truth and eternal illusion seem to exist independently of one another, producing the cosmos out of their joint energy.
Vallabha and his followers went so far as to dub Shankara a M!y!v!da, a believer in Maya as if illusion was the ultimate driving force in the cosmos. Vallabha tried to purify Shankara s non-dualism by insisting that Maya was simply a power (.akti) possessed by Brahman. Brahman thus creates the world himself using this power, rather than sitting inert while being acted upon by it (it is common to use the male pronoun he in discussing Vallabha s Brahman, as Brahman is most typically figured as Krishna). Brahman gives rise to the world out of his own will (icch!) and his joyful sense of play (l$l!). Notably, nothing is created or destroyed in the making of the world. Aspects of Brahman are simply concealed (tirobh!va) in order to produce the differences endemic to the cosmos. Vallabha delineates three major aspects of the
Supreme Being: truth (sat), awareness (cit), and bliss (!nanda). He then details which of these are apparent and which concealed in various worldly forms (e.g. in the jagat, or material world, sat is manifest, while cit and !nanda are hidden; in the soul, sat and cit are both manifest, while !nanda remains hidden). The technical details of Vallabha s monism are less important to the present discussion, however, than his mystical apprehension of cosmic oneness. To his mind, the soul is just a fragment of Brahman, a spark from his fire.[280]
Maharaj Jadunathji Brizratanji was in full agreement. The essays in his journal, the Propagator, assiduously fuse the material and the spiritual in a rigorously advaitic vein. In this world, Jadunath explains, every form is made from God s own parts (sarve r+p $.var pote an. kar$ne thay! che). Indeed, the world is simply God at play with himself (pote rama* kare che).[281] To take this claim seriously means that a mother s love for her child is not simply like her love for Krishna; when she loves her child, she is loving Krishna. The child is simply a spark from the god s divine fire. Following Leela Gandhi, one might say that it is by confusing the empirical and the metaphysical that bhakti unmoors the subject, securing its affective surrender both to divine and human others. The individual soul is not only predicated on the ontological priority of the divine; it is subsumed by the divine s pantheistic extension into the material world. The Advaitic confusion of the material and the spiritual was a source of great consternation to the court, which saw only moral catastrophe in the idea that adulterous couplings might be described as God at play with his own spirit (MLC, 4950). In his closing remarks, Anstey pronounced the modern doctrines of the Pu()im!rg to be monstrous insofar as they supersede the ancient doctrines of morality. If the Maharajas are but extensions of God and his lila, then they cannot be held individually accountable for their misdeeds. The god this atrocious hypocrite, the Maharaj is simply at amorous dalliance with his own spirit! (369). Without metaphysical justification for the doctrine of the discrete subject, Anstey implies, anyone can do anything, however immoral and abominable. Still worse, advaitic ontology erodes the epistemological certainties of empiricism. According to Anstey, the doctrine of the maya delusion leads devotees to mistrust their own sensory perceptions, particularly in matters involving the faults of the guru himself. They thus subordinate their critical faculties to the guru s authority (371, 376). Sensory perception here undergirds liberal autonomy, and Vallabha s metaphysics undoes both simultaneously. The justice of the court was based on these two very entities (accuracy of evidence and individual culpability), and so, for the trial to proceed, the Advaitic challenge to both had to be dismissed.
During the trial, bhakti s ethics of self-surrender was seriously challenged. Indeed it seems likely that Vallabha s call for radical relationality had, by the 1850s, come to undergird devotional practices in dire need of critique. The Maharaj Libel Affair fixated on two devotional affects, the j"r bh"va ( adulterine love ) and the d"sya bh"va ( slavishness ). Each of these threatened the self-contained liberal subject much more vividly than did the other bh"vas. The scandal took the two up in tandem.
Rotating tableaux of erotic debasement were presented to the court for dispassionate adjudication. Physical intimacies bled together: the guru s sexual liberties with Pu()im!rg$ girls and his Holi gropings; devotees desire to drink the dirty water in which he washed his feet and dhoti and to chew his old p!n.[282] Religion, sex, and power converged in the Maharaj Libel Case to render the scandal an unusually titillating chapter in the history of priestcraft. The following two sections will discuss the j"r bh"va and the d"sya bh"va respectively.
The Vallabhac!rya samprad!ya had emphasized the rich relationality of the human subject by cataloguing and sanctifying several kinds of love (master-servant, parent-child, friend-friend, wife-husband, lover-lover). In doing so, it inevitably entangled its devotional prescriptions within the actual gender economies of Pu()im!rg$ homes. During the nineteenth century, domestic space was reconfigured by the colonial usurpation of the public. In consequence, traditional gender practices came into view as something open to alteration. The Hindu woman was more than just one possible object of reform; she was in many ways the quintessential such object, her domestic spaces the crucial meeting ground of religion, nation, and popular culture. The Maharaj Libel Affair s scandalized panic over what might be termed gopi morality needs to be understood within this historical context.
Much has been said about the place of sexuality in the Maharaj Libel Affair. As J rgen L tt suggested, the 1860s were a pivotal period for the repression of Vai(*ava erotics.77 Hindu reformists, informed by both Victorian and brahmac!rya mores, put public sexuality under increasing pressure during the latter part of the nineteenth century and, as feminist historians have astutely reminded us, they did so as part of a broader intervention into the gender economies of the Hindu home.78 Usha Thakkar has shown how the Maharaj Libel Case staged its conflict between tradition and modernity on the silenced bodies of bourgeois women.79 As Amrita Shodhan has further clarified, the scandal prompted a transfer of patriarchal control from priests to families. With the temple now seen as a site of sexual corruption, husbands and fathers began to keep their women at home.80 The conjuncture of gender and Gujarati reformism dated to the 1850s and, in particular, to the 1857 founding of the journal Stree Bodh. Mulji had been heavily involved in this publication, which collected short stories and educational essays on diverse topics for consumption by Gujarati women. For example, in perusing the January 1861 issue, a woman could learn about South
American slave markets, the emperors of China and Austria, the greatness of the
77 L tt. From Krishna-Lila to Ram-Rajya
78 See Kumkum Sangari and Sudesh Vaid, eds, Recasting Women: Essays in Indian Colonial History (New
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1990); Partha Chatterjee, The Nation and Its Fragments: Colonial and
Postcolonial Histories (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993); Tanika Sarkar, Hindu Wife, Hindu Nation: Community, Religion, and Cultural Nationalism (New Delhi: Permanent Black, 2001). Bourgeois Muslim men launched a parallel effort. See, for instance, Perfecting Women: Maulana Ashraf ,Al( Thanawi's Bihishti Zewar (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990).
79 Usha Thakkar, Puppets on the Periphery: Women and Social Reform in 19th Century Gujarati Society, Economic and Political Weekly 32.1-2 (January 4-11, 1997): 46-58.
80 Amrita Shodhan, Women in the Maharaja Libel Case: A Re-examination, Indian Journal of Gender Studies 4:2 (1997): 123-139.
ancient Greeks, women in Italy and Africa, William Penn, or the kangaroo. She could also delve into topics of more practical relevance to her daily life, such as how to make friends or how to be critical of superstitious tales (vahem) about ghosts and witches.[283] The presumption that drove journals like Stree Bodh was that, in order for India to be reformed, its women had to lead the way.
Male sexuality too came under a renewed scrutiny. Traditionally, male devotees had cultivated their desire for Krishna by imaging themselves as gopis, the female cowherds who sported amorously with the young god. As Anstey summarized in his opening plea, members of the sect cultivated humbleness before the guru by believing that he the said member is not a man, but a woman servant of such leader. In God, the two species of man and woman do not exist (MLC, 47-50). The love between Krishna and the gopis was paradigmatic of the madhura bh!va, or honeyed romantic love, central to Vaisnava bhakti movements. There were generally held to be three different kinds of gopi. First are the gopis who were the objects of Krishna s childhood pranks; their feeling for the Lord aligns more closely with v!tsalya than madhura bh!va. Second are the unmarried gopis who hope to wed Sri Krishna; with R!dha as their ringleader, their licit love remains within the fold of familial propriety. Third are the married gopis, whose desire flouts social mores, moral codes, and even religious laws. Their all-consuming love exemplifies devotion impatient to transgress worldly limitations.[284] This was the adulterine love, or j"r bh"va, that proved so scandalous in the nineteenth century.
By 1860, adulterous love had come to seem a dubious virtue. Even in the first issue of the Propagator, a defensive Jadunathji intently evacuates bhakti of its erotic content. Many people, he writes, have misunderstood the sakhya bh!va by taking friendship (mitrat!) to be something sinful (du(an) and undiscriminating (avivek). It is, he assures us, simply the practice of loving the Lord s form just like you love a friend and feeling anxious longing like you would for a friend would when you do his darshan.[285] The second issue retranslates the key terms: sakhya means friendship (mitrat!), and bhakti love (sneh). While worshipping Krishna, the devotee is to experience an anxious desire (!t+rt!) for the Dark Lord; alternately, he or she might experience v!tsalt!, the doting love that a parent feels for a child. Jadunathji wants to guard against the imputation that Pu()im!rg$s worship God (bhagv!n) with the j!rbh!va, the adulterine emotion. He angrily dismisses as fools those who would make such an allegation; they have dirtied bhakti and are thus immoral (an$tin$) and irreligious (adharmn$). To love God adulterously is, he assures his reader, a sin.
Jadunathji tidies up the gopis love for Krishna by insisting that they were avatars of Parvati come for Mahadev, Sitaji for Sri Ram. Gopi love is marital love: where is the sin in this?[286]
Mulji s allegations against the Maharaj brought this gopi morality before the public eye, and added an extra twist to it. According to Mulji, devotees ethereal love for Krishna had been debased by heterodox sexual practices. Mulji railed against a Sanskrit verse that said it was the duty (kartavya) of devotees to give all their belongings (sarvavastu) to the guru before enjoying them themselves
(svopabhog!tp+rvameva). As his Gujarati translation scandalously emphasized, belongings was to include women; wives were to be offered (sopvu) to the Maharaj before being enjoyed by their husbands (bhogve! pehel!). This teaching, Mulji wrote, was pure and simple fraud ()hag!$).[287] The allegation that Pu()im!rg$ women had performed their worship, implicit obedience and service via carnal intercourse was the central allegation during the libel trial, and it was cinched by Dr. Bhau Daji s account of the Maharaj s struggle with syphilis (MLC, 45). It seems that, within the Pu()im!rg, self-surrender (!tm!-nivedan) had come to be enacted symbolically using gifts as indexical substitutes for the devotee. Prayer, desire, and anxious longing for the Lord came to be triangulated through these objects of exchange and most notably, or so the allegations went, through the exchange of women. Pu()im!rg$ men averted cross-sex identification and same-sex desire by forcing (or perhaps allowing)
Pu()im!rg$ women to enact the love-game with Krishna for them.
Or such, at least, was Mulji s allegation. Regardless, it is clear that by the 1850s, all parties had come to distance themselves publicly from the more challenging ethical precepts of the Vallabhac!rya samprad!ya. If the erotic represented the limit to the self-possessed subject, the erotic was what would have to be excised for religion to endear itself to reason. My argument in the two previous sections has, in many ways, echoed Behramji M. Malabari 1889 description of the Maharajism. With a breezy tone, Malabari condemns that disturber of social virtue, the Vallabhac!ryan Maharaj and praises Mulji, the truly enlightened Bania reformer. [288] Although he cannot fathom the incomprehensible psychological phenomenon of Pu()im!rg$ devotion,[289] he remains sympathetic to what he sees as the original ideals of bhakti. As he puts it,
What is the meaning of Maharaj worship? The idea originally meant to portray the soul s yearning for its Creator, more intense than the mother s love for her child, more passionate than the attachment subsisting between man and wife, between the two that are but one.[290]
Malabari admires this beautiful idea, while criticizing contemporary practice. In the previous discussion, I hope to have demonstrated that this ideal was not lost to the Vallabhac!rya samprad!ya of the 1850s and 60s; it continued to inform how the sect presented itself. Reading bhakti texts alongside the court record allows those texts to emerge as a criticism of the liberal selves enjoined by the legal system.
At the heart of the Maharaj Libel Case was a single troubling proposition: Guru
is God. The proposition, framed by the court, reduced the rich relational web of bhakti devotion to a single theological claim, a statement of abstract fact to which one either did or did not assent. In this, the claim was fully amenable to the managerial imperatives of the colonial state and its bureaucratic Hinduism. As would become clear during the course of the trial, however, this particular proposition tended to exceed the use to which the court put it. It dictates the relationship between two entities ( Guru and God), establishing the sacred equivalence of Krishna and his incarnation, the Maharaj; but it also inevitably refers to a third entity, the believing subject. When the court asked witnesses whether they believed Guru to be God, what it wanted to know was how they believed in the guru. With what sense of hierarchy? With what intensity of affect? Guru is God is a troubling proposition for anticlerical modernity because it returns theology to the arena of sociality its antiseptic abstraction cannot be divorced from the affective attachments of human relationships, nor is its claim to faith separable from the fiduciary, the loving trust in the other that is the ether of the social bond.
The claim Guru is God was highly overdetermined during the trial. Thus, not surprisingly, in a courtroom where the ramifications of assenting to this proposition were under extreme scrutiny and anything but predictable, witnesses found themselves in a very uncomfortable position. Take, for instance, the testimony of Jumnadas Sevaklal. At first, he hesitated. But after being threatened with a fine of one hundred rupees, he finally capitulated to Anstey s aggressive interrogation. As he explained, carefully detailing the meanings of his terms: By God I mean Krishna . In my opinion, the Maharaj is a representative of Krishna. This clarification, however, did not suffice:
Mr. Anstey Do some Banias believe the Maharaj to be a God?
Witness We consider him to be our gooroo.
Sir. M. Sausse Tell witness if he does not answer the question, he will be sent to
jail.
Witness What is the precise question? (Interpreter explains) Some consider the
Maharaj a god in the shape of gooroo.
Mr. Anstey Is Gooroo a God?
Witness Gooroo is gooroo.
Sir M. Sausse Tell him if he does not answer the question, most indubitably he
will go to jail.
Sir Joseph Arnould Tell him he is asked what others believe, not as to his own
belief.
Witness I don t know if others believe him as God; I consider him simply a gooroo.
The examination continues, and Sevaklal is eventually fined fifty rupees for his unsatisfactory answers (MLC, 134-36).
Several intersecting imperatives converge on this testimony, signaling Sevaklal s reticence as an emblematic moment in the trial. Sevaklal is invited to speak as a specimen of his caste; that is, he speaks doubly for himself and for a collectivity, his own private beliefs evidence of the religious customs of the Banias more generally.
Indeed, the court defers to Sevaklal s reticence in confessing his own faith (the
Bombay High Court is not, after all the Inquisition); rather, it wants simply to
determine the public question of what patterns of belief prevail within the
Pu()im!rg. Belief becomes an ethnological property.
Thus, in the conditions of its utterance, belief belies the modern mythos of religious interiority and autonomy: belief is solicited by power in order to situate individuals within collectivities. Sevaklal s testimony may be an extreme instance; but, as several theorists have suggested, a similar dynamic structures most (and likely all) attestations of belief. Ludwig Wittgenstein has explained that a claim to belief establishes a relation between a person and a proposition. Despite referencing an internal state, the claim is always already oriented outward toward the language game that lends it meaning and defines its stakes.[291] These games are often, and certainly in matters of religion, deeply implicated in political structures. As Simon During put it in his study of modern magic, to declare one s belief or disbelief in magic is to position oneself in relation to the discursive web of rationality, civility, and enlightenment, and in a context where it is difficult to be a fully rational citizen and to declare a serious belief in magic. [292] Belief situates the believer. Sevaklal could assent to the proposition Guru is God and exclude himself from the Anglo-Indian public, or he could dissent from it and exclude himself from the Bania caste polity. Gauri Viswanathan argues that colonial conjunctures like this one reveal the insufficiencies endemic to modern notions of religious belief more broadly: even as liberal discourse upholds a notion of individual subjectivity as the emergence of the free, private self under bourgeois capitalism, the colonial context denies that such a notion can be accommodated by the logic of institutionalized social practices. [293] Here, foremost among these practices was that of cross-examination itself. Anstey repeatedly suggested that, because the plaintiff s witnesses had been unduly influenced by Jadunathji s charismatic authority, their wholly partial and interested evidence was invalid and should be dismissed (MLC, 375).[294] Despite itself, the cross-examination implies that belief is always, in a sense, coerced that is, solicited by structures external to the believing subject
In other words, even propositional belief needs to be understood as, at bottom, relational in nature. I would tentatively suggest that Sevaklal knew this implicitly. His tautological insistence that Guru is Guru was, at second glance, one of the more astute comments made during the trial. Precisely as a guru, the Maharaj could invite the sort hierarchical devotion that the court and Mulji found so alarming. When Mulji professed that he never believed in Jadunath s divinity, even though he was and is
one of those who believe in the Maharaj as a guru, he rather missed the point (MLC, 190). Propositional belief does not determine the form of relational belief. The affective intensity of the latter is relatively independent of theological claims.
As I suggested above, Vallabhac!rya s regimen of bhakti devotion sanctified the dense web of human relations indeed it elevated the ethical act of self-surrender to the beloved as the quintessential devotional act. The court, on the other hand, split bhakti relationality in two. Half of it was returned to devotees as propositional belief, the sort of faith that one has, rather than the sort of faith that possesses the believer (Derrida s fiduciary). The other half was, via libel law, returned to the Maharaj as his reputation.
As Sean Latham has put it, the civil law of torts provides a legal forum where truth can be separated from fiction and where those who use mass media s power to disseminate lies can be called publicly to account. [295] The law of torts also, I would suggest, does more than this. Specifically, as I will argue in this final section of the chapter, during the Maharaj Libel Case the question of charisma was rendered as a question of reputation. Where charisma implies the affective intensities of bhakti devotion outlined above, reputation is much cooler legal category. Bhakti askesis facilitated the undoing of the self-identical subject through acts of loving surrender to the divine other (i.e atmanivedan); the legal concept reputation, on the other hand, returned sociality to the subject as a form of personal property that reinforces selfidentity. Because a spiritual person by definition could not be libeled (the spiritual is constitutively public), Jadunathji had to file suit as a private citizen. But in doing so, he shifted the terms of the debate about the ethical possibilities opened by Krishna devotion. In the following discussion, I will sketch a short history of libel law before returning to the concept reputation.
The Indian Penal Code of 1860 would have governed the Bombay High Court s inquiry into the alleged libel charges. Although the roots of Anglo-Indian libel law could be traced back to the ancient Mediterranean world, and even to the dawn of writing itself, its most important principles were of more recent derivation.[296] The tort of defamation was substantially refined by both the Reform Act of 1832 and the Libel
Act of 1843. These pieces of legislation created new protections for those who criticized public persons and also articulated the principle of justification that was enshrined in the Indian Penal Code. For a libel to be justified, it had to be proved by the defendant that its allegations were true and that their publication was in the public interest.[297]
Both were upheld in the case of Mulji s libel.
Libel law was, not surprisingly, held to be of particular pertinence to newspapers. The press was bound by two discourses: the law of defamation and the duty to publish (a moral code identified in Chapter 2 as part of the Whig-McLuhanite narrative of print media).[298] Papers that followed the latter imperative without proper attention to the former were likely to end up in court. Legal regulations about what constituted publication are of some interest.[299] It was generally held that, in the case of newspapers, the moment of sale constituted the act of publication ( tale-bearers are as bad as tale-makers ). Distributors were seldom held liable for the contents of the newspapers that they sold, but everyone involved in the production process was vulnerable to a libel suit, including the proprietor, editor, printer, and publisher.[300] Additionally, the definition of publication was open-ended enough to include less formal communications like letters.[301] As one legal guide puts it, [c]ommunicating defamatory matter to some person other than the person of whom it is written is publication in the legal sense you cannot publish a libel of a man to himself. [302]
This is because libel pertains to how a person is perceived by others that is, speech is defamatory insofar as it affects reputation. In the words of the 1860 Indian Penal Code, in the estimation of others, [it] lowers the moral or intellectual character of that person, or lowers the character of that person in respect of his caste or of his calling, or lowers the credit of that person, or causes it to be believed that the body of that person is in a loathsome state, or in a state generally considered as disgraceful. [303]
In other words, reputation distills the complex web of an individual s social and professional relationships into a discrete object. It reifies a community s fluid perceptions so that the person can hold them as a form of property. In a sense, reputation inverts the process whereby a subject is hailed by her social order and offered a fixed position within it: one has a reputation, rather than being had by it.
In the estimation of one legal guide, reputation is if possible, more valuable than other property. No mere poetic fancy suggested the truth that a good name is rather to be chosen than great riches. This special form of property requires a special form of regulation. Every man has an absolute right to have his reputation preserved inviolate. [304] If anyone deprives a person of a reputation to which he or she has a right, the wronged party can sue for defamation. But there is a crucial caveat to this rule. The law will not permit a man to recover damages in respect of an injury to a character that he does not, or ought not, to possess. [305] In other words, it is possible for a person to claim a reputation wrongly. This is a public crime, but not necessarily one open to police intervention. It is becomes the duty of public actors like journalists to regulate the representational property of reputation. The law promises implicitly to reinforce their regulatory authority, if they have acted properly.
When Jadunathji sued Mulji for libel, he had to claim damages to his reputation. As I suggested above, this claim implied a concept of the religious person very different from that implied by the claim that guru is god that is, an incarnation of Krishna. In Pu()im!rg$ tradition, the guru s sanctity was inscribed in his body, an effect of his blood descent from Vallabha; Jadunathji Brizratanji was a guru through and through. In the eyes of the law, on the other hand, guru was a public office held by the man Jadunath Brizratan; by definition, he was distinct from his office. In court, the private person carried rights denied to spiritual person. The notion that Jadunathji had a split self was ubiquitous in the trial, as in Bayley s claim that Mulji had libeled the plaintiff in his double capacity as man and as Maharaj (MLC, 167).
The precise nature of the spiritual person proved a point of contention during the trial. There was some sense that, in his spiritual capacity as Maharaj, Jadunathji was a public person and therefore not protected by the tort of defamation. Anstey, the defense attorney, also argued that there was no law of defamation of a spiritual man in British India because there was no precedent for a spiritual man suing for libel. There had been no such suit in Bombay, and in England such a suit would fall into the purview of the ecclesiastical court.[306] The novelty of a priest even appearing in court was evident throughout the trial, as in the imbroglios leading up to it: Jadunathji had broken with custom when, rather than defiantly avoiding subpoenas, he actually volunteered himself for a court appearance. Bayley, the prosecuting attorney, countered by insisting that if a spiritual man cannot sue to protect his reputation, then no Brahmin in the land would be safe; he could be slandered and libeled with impunity, and redress denied to him because he happened to be a spiritual person (MLC, 31-32). Even so, the prosecution seemed to think it safer to argue that the
Jadunathji had been defamed in his private character, not his spiritual capacity (170). In other words, even gods were privatized by the British court. Religion was, as I have been suggesting, fundamentally refigured by the trial.
After the trial, Jadunathji Brizratanji and several other Maharajas quickly left Bombay, lest they be indicted for perjury.[307] A new crop of primers on libel law, like Jehangeer Merwanjee s exceedingly comprehensive Gujarati guide, entered the book market.[308] Meanwhile, Mulji was feted for several months by his fellow reformists.[309]
Eventually, however, he too moved on to new challenges most notably, a trip to
England that got him banned from the Bania caste.
Many had predicted that the trial would extinguish belief in the Maharaj.[310] But the actual impact of scandalous publicity seems to have been much more ambivalent. During the trial, Anstey claimed that while the public s love for Jadunathji had diminished, their respect had not (MLC, 152). Others pointed out that much of the community had mistrusted the Maharajas for decades; the trial only told people what they already knew. As for the believers, the Poona Observer noted that the scandal had
only increased the ardour of their devotion.[311]
I would suggest that the real effects of the Maharaj Libel Affair were in a domain other than that of belief. Because of the case s scandalous notoriety, fraud and priestcraft rose to renewed prominence as the choicest invectives for traducing religion. For example, in the early 1860s a separate scandal was brewing within another of Bombay s Gujarati communities: the Khojas. This Muslim community was split over the figure of the Agha Khan, who had come to western India from Persia in the 1840s. Many Khojas accepted the Agha Khan as their spiritual and temporal leader, and they allowed him to bring their hybrid religious practice in line with Ismaeli norms. A significant minority, however, resented the Agha Khan s influence, and they proclaimed themselves orthodox Sunnis in order to thwart his authority claims. Property disputes and rumors about a sensational murder brought the Khojas before the print public and before the court.[312] Particularly in the former, the imposture theory was used to narrate the contest among critics, disciples, and charismatic authority. The Anglophone press compared and even conflated the Khoja and
Pu()im!rg$ controversies, as when the Poona Observer referenced the evil rites of the
Khojah Maharajahs. [313] An 1864 pamphlet, written by a Khoja in London, followed in a this vein by comparing the Agha Khan to the Pope: he practices imposture upon the credulity of the uneducated class, who in their superstitious infatuation believe him
to be a personification of God. 112
In the next chapter, I will discuss how the polemics of priestcraft shaped the work of famed Hindu reformer Sw!m$ Day!nanda Sarasvat$. As I will suggest, his translation of priestcraft as pope-lila plays a central role in his 1875 opus, the
Saty"rth Prak"sh. The links between Karsandas and Dayanand are legion. Both men were
Gujaratis. Both chose to write in Hindi; Dayanand may have been influenced by Karsandas advocacy of the national language in his late tract Ved Dharm. Both championed the Vedas and tried to peel away the heterodox accretions of priestly Hinduism. Both worked with the same cadre of reformists in Bombay; Mulji s inner circle would go on to help found Dayanand s Arya Samaj thirteen years later.113 As several scholars have noted, the Maharaj Libel Case was likely a major influence on Dayanand; when the scandal broke, he was studying in Mathura, the epicenter of Krishna consciousness. In his later work, Dayanand would reserve his harshest invectives for the Maharajas of the Pu()im!rg, often recycling the major allegations from the trial (the surrender of tan man dhan; the contraction of sexually transmitted
not half so wicked; the rites of the Khojah Maharajahs are not half so evil in their results as the prepaying of postage. It is really bad. Poona Observer, December 10, 1861
112 A Voice from India, Being an Appeal to the British Legislature by Khojahs of Bombay, against the
Usurped and Oppressive Domination of Hussain Hussanee, Commonly Called and Known as Aga Khan
(London: Waterlow and Sons, 1864), 5. The pamphlet is anonymous; the author simply bills himself as a
Native of Bombay, Now Resident in London.
113 Dobbin, 254-256.
infections; the guru s reliance on nets of delusion
[mithy!-j!l]).[314] Most strikingly, the title of
Dayanand s book, the Saty"rth Prak"sh, echoes that of
Karsandas newspaper, the Satya Prak"sh.
The spiritual life of Sw!m$ Day!nanda Saraswat$ (1824-1883) began the night he lost his faith. One fateful boyhood evening, he followed his father to the temple to keep the vigil of "ivar!tr$. Late that night, while his father and the other devotees snoozed, he watched a mouse scramble over the stone image of Shiva and munch on the god s pras"dam. As the rodent clambered across the unprotesting deity, the boy (not yet Dayanand) had a revelation: the dumb matter of the m+rti could not be divine. Something changed in his heart that night, and although when he left the temple he returned home to his mother, it would not be long before he abandoned his family entirely. The mouse had made him a man, and as man (born again under a renunciant s name) he resolved to take on the mouse s mantle: he would travel India, exploding ritual illusions to bring his countrymen to the truth of transcendent religion.[315]
Dayanand s was an intolerant, fundamentalist orthodoxy, and during his period of greatest activity (c.1872-1883), he lashed his opponents Hindu and Jain, Christian and Muslim with acerbic, unbending polemics, in print and in person. [316] He published his major written work, the Saty"rth Prak"# (Light of Truth), in 1875. Now reckoned the bible of the %rya Sam!j (the religious association founded by Dayanand), the book proffers a disenchanted Hinduism with a decidedly empirical ethos, firmly divorcing
the transcendent divine from the material world.
In this chapter, I argue that Dayanand centered the Saty"rth Prak"sh on a translation of the term priestcraft. I pay particular attention to the eleventh chapter of Dayanand s polemic text, which I take to be the most important chapter for delineating the devotional stakes of his proposed reform. Totaling over one hundred pages, it is by far the longest chapter in the Saty"rth Prak"sh. Its exhaustive discussion of religious error not only preempts much of the polemic to follow (the remaining three chapters vituperate against Jains, Christians, and Muslims respectively); it also resituates the neo-Vedic beliefs and disciplines laid in the first ten chapters. Where other scholars have looked to the Saty"rth Prak"sh for its contributions to communalist invective or the formation of a neo-orthodox scriptural canon, I will consider how Dayanand s eminently polemic text uses this historical narrative to articulate an alternative anticlerical modernity that takes a reconstituted Hinduism as its native domain.
My reading of the Saty"rth Prak"sh unfolds from one particularly curious passage. Dayanand, whose rhetorical skills were honed in the arena of public debate, peppers his first book with fictive dialogues. One such dialogue features the following singular interchange:
Dayanand: But you are not a brahman.
Interlocutor: So who am I?
Dayanand: You are a Pope (tum pop ho). [317]
Here Dayanand dismisses his Hindu nemeses with a curiously hybrid accusation: tum pop ho. He proceeds to elaborate this insult by introducing another critical and critically hybrid term: pope-l$l!.
Pope-lila serves, in its way, as a translation of the term priestcraft discussed in the previous chapters of this dissertation. With this translation, Dayanand quite cannily invokes a rich register of polemic English, honed by centuries of slander against alleged charlatans and deployed throughout the nineteenth century to chart divine fakeries worldwide and especially in India. But pope-lila is, of course, only as a partial translation of priestcraft and popery. Pope is transposed from English into Hindi and paired with lila, a term with a sense very different from that of craft and craftiness. Pope-lila functions then not so much as a translation of priestcraft, but rather as a creative adaptation of a term redolent with the mythologies of modernity.[318]
The central argument of this chapter is that pope-lila proves a uniquely productive term for Dayanand because it allows him to marshal two critical traditions (one British, one Indian) without rendering him beholden to either.[319] The interstitial space that he opens allows Dayanand critical purchase on each of these only by granting him access to the critical vocabularies honed by the other. Although
Dayanand s ultimate goal is to establish the Vedas as the transcendent platform for the critical appraisal of all religions, Indian and otherwise, my analysis in this chapter will, repeatedly, seek to arrest Dayanand en route to the universal and transcendent, to catch him in the provisional moment of critique, which is where I think he is at his most interesting. Hence the chapter s focus, its opening note, is not the pristine purity of the Vedas, but rather the earthy ambivalence of pope-lila.
The chapter is structured as follows. First, I outline the broad contours of Dayanand s career and the Vedic modernity that he articulated, offering a short survey of existing scholarship in the process. Second ( Imposture Theory I ), I introduce the concept of pope-lila. I note how Dayanand uses the concept to offer an account of the religious history of Europe and how he then asserts an easy equivalence between
European and Indian popes. Briefly contrasting Dayanand s Sartyarth Prakash with
William Howitt s A History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (1833), I note how
Dayanand anchors his notion of pope-lila in an event (the epic battle from the
Mah"bh"rata) and a theological concept (the avat!r) drawn from Hindu tradition. Finally, I further note how pope-lila allows Dayanand to speculate about the technological accomplishments of the ancient Aryans and also to cast his heterodox opponents into semantic exile by transforming them into foreign popes.
The third section ( Truth and the Nation ) outlines the history of India that Dayanand includes in Chapter 11 of the Saty"rth Prak"sh. I draw on Gyan Prakash s analysis of the irruptive archaic temporality of the Vedic nation to argue that, for Dayanand, pure truth is fundamentally pre-historical, and the Hindu nation proper is founded on a lie. The perennial eruptions of truth propel this history dialectically, as scheming popes revise their lies to subsume and pervert truthful criticisms. The lie thus comes to serve a supremely productive function, as it is what drives history. Next ( Subaltern Skeptics ), I ask how Dayanand uses the narrative form of the dialogue to co-opt different critical positions into his Vedic program. I examine at length a tale about a J!) who comes to see through the ruses of the popes, and then I argue that Dayanand never quite manages to consolidate such tales into the dominant authorial voice of the Saty"rth Prak"sh. At the same time that Dayanand s book reduced oral tales to writing, the circulating print artifact remained embedded within networks of oral exchange. To substantiate this claim, I trace the circulation of a story about nosecutters.
Fifth ( Imposture Theory II ), I ask how the strategy of critical cooptation determined Dayanand s use of the concept pope-lila itself. I suggest that a major piece of Dayanand s program in the eleventh chapter of the Saty"rth Prak"sh was to reclaim the great philosopher "a#kar!c!rya (henceforth Shankara) away from the philosophical school that he founded. Advaita Ved!nta s strict monism had undermined the empirical certitudes of this world, and Dayanand was determined to limit the illusions plied by thinkers in that tradition. He used the term pope-lila tendentiously to argue that illusion is always human (the product of popes) and never divine (the product of cosmic m!y!). Dayanand reclaims Shankara from non-dualism by collapsing his metaphysics into his rhetoric: all his ontological musings were just a tactical tool in his polemical contest with the Jains. Finally ( The Criticism of Religions ), I interpret the parliament of religions with which Dayanand concludes his history of Hinduism. Dayanand distances himself from the arena of interreligious debate (matmat!ntar viv!d), using the Vedas to claim transcendent authority. I read his fable against the grain, arguing that it highlights the productive capacity of the lie. If anything transcends the immanent plane of interreligious debate, it is truth as absence, that which prods the proliferation of religious speech.[320]
The
boy who would be Dayanand was born in 1824 to a brahman family in Gujarat s
Kathiawar peninsula.[321] His father insisted that, from a
young age, his son adhere to a strict devotional regimen; and at least until
his encounter with the mouse, Dayanand did not question his unusually
scrupulous religious observance.[322] After that night, however, he grew
increasingly distant from his family. A few years later, having refused his
parents efforts to marry him off, he ran away from home to pursue the life
of a wandering renunciant. After several years, he came to Mathura (the great center of Krishna devotion) where, from 1860 till 1863, he studied under the blind grammarian, Swami V$raj!nanda a man whose dislike of modern learning was so acute that he only agreed to teach P!*ini to Dayanand once he had drowned all his own books in the Yamuna.[323] This period was the second decisive event in Dayanand s life. The third was his 1872 trip to Calcutta, at the invitation of Debendranath Tagore. After four months hobnobbing with the city s reformist elite (including notable Brahmo Samajis like Keshab Chander Sen), Dayanand was a changed man. He resolved to abandon his loincloth and his learned Sanskrit in favor of ordinary clothes and Hindi, a new language for him and one politically on the rise in the 1870s. Henceforth, Dayanand would be a populist reformer committed to a new kind of religion.[324]
The next ten years moved quickly for Dayanand. In 1873, during a visit to Sayyid Ahmad Khan, Aligarh s district collector Raja Jai Kishen Das urged him to write a book about his teachings.[325] Dayanand took the advice and completed the Saty"rth Prak"sh in 1874 while living in Allahabad; it was published in 1875.[326] Also in 1875, he traveled to
Bombay, where he founded the Arya Samaj on the model of the Brahmo Samaj and
Bombay s Pr!rthana Sam!j. In 1877, while in Delhi for the Durbar proclaiming Queen
Victoria the Kaiser-i-Hind, he was invited to visit Punjab, the region that would prove the most fertile field for his ideas.[327] After his death in 1883, the Arya Samaj continued to expand and formalize its institutions; in 1887, it opened the Dayananda Anglo-Vedic College in Lahore.
The success of the Arya Samaj has driven scholarly interest in Dayanand. As early as 1914, John Nichol Farquhar granted the society pride of place in his discussion of modern religious movements committed to defence of the old faiths. [328] Kenneth
Jones pioneering 1976 study further developed this basic paradigm by examining how Punjabi Hindus made use of the Arya Samaj to negotiate between colonial and traditional cultural frames.[329] More recently, scholars have debated Dayanand s influence on twentieth century Hindu nationalism. Arya Samajis were prominent in the creation of the All-India Hindu Mah!sabh!, and Dayanand s attempted restoration of the Aryan nation resonates unmistakably with the ideals of Hindutva propounded by V. D. S!varkar (1883-1966) and others. While many scholars have argued for a direct connection between nineteenth century reform movements and twentieth century communalism, others have preferred to emphasize the discontinuity between these two distinct historical moments.[330] In either case, it is also clear Arya Samaj that reform programs contributed to the nationalist reconstitution of race and gender ideologies, and to debates over the woman question in late colonial Punjab.17
More important to the present discussion, however, is how Dayanand intervened in the religious debates of the nineteenth century. He articulated a selfconsciously rational Hinduism that proudly returned to Vedic origins. He was not the first reformer to advocate such a revivified Hinduism (Karsandas Mulji is a clear precedent; see Chapter 3); but his twist on this popular pattern would prove particularly influential. Like other Hindu intelligentsia of the period, he denied the Western origin of science by claiming a Vedic provenance for scientific knowledge and technical expertise.18 At the same time, he reshaped the Hindu scriptural canon itself or, rather, as J. E. Llewellyn has suggested, he borrowed classificatory procedures from Virajanand (the blind grammarian) in order to sort and consolidate the canon. In the process, he granted the Vedas a practical importance that they had previously lacked. 19
Prak"sh; see Christophe Jaffrelot, Hindu Nationalism: A Reader (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007). In the other camp, John Zavos has emphasized the importance of the ideological dislocation of the 1920s. See John Zavos, The Arya Samaj and the Antecedents of Hindu Nationalism, International Journal of Hindu Studies 3:1 (April 1999): 57-81. For another revisionist argument that also emphasizes the 1920s, see Catherine Adcock, Religious Freedom and Political Culture: The Arya Samaj in Colonial North India (Ph.D. diss., University of Chicago, 2007).
17 The ambiguities entailed by Dayanand s Aryanism have been explored by Romila Thapar, The Theory of Aryan Race and India: History and Politics, Social Scientist, 24.1/3 (November 1996): 3-29; and Dorothy Matilda Figueira, Aryans, Jews, Brahmins: Theorizing Authority through Myths of Identity (Albany: SUNY Press, 2002). For gender in Punjab, see Anshu Malhotra, The Moral Woman and the Urban Punjabi Society of the Late Nineteenth Century, Social Scientist 20.5/6 (May-June 1992): 34-63; and Anshu Malhotra, Every Woman is a Mother in Embryo: Lala Lajpat Rai and Indian Womanhood, Social Scientist, 22.1/2 (JanuaryFebruary 1994): 40-63.
18 Gyan Prakash, Another Reason: Science and the Imagination of Modern India (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999), 86.
19 Llewellyn, Arya Samaj, 30-34.
Mostly, however, he remained haunted by the mouse that forever changed his perception of Shaiva ritualism. In order to spread his revelation, he would have to make like the mouse and expose the illusions of material religion. His chief means of doing so was through public debates, through polemical force and rhetorical wordplay. In the Saty"rth Prak"sh, one wordplay in particular distills Dayanand s persistent concern with priestly illusion.
Imposture Theory I: Popes or Brahmans?
Dayanand wrote most of the Saty"rth Prak"sh in a primly Sanskritized Hindi. Indeed, when he wrote it, he had only recently deigned to switch from Sanskrit to the vernacular. As a consequence, his decision to make central use of an English word in his history of Indian religions is particularly notable. Dayanand claims that most contemporary brahmans are brahmans in name only (they are n!m-m!tra brahmans); it is therefore not appropriate (yogya) to serve them or even to call them by the name brahman. Dayanand provides these imposters with a new epithet in an accusatory dialogue: But you are not a brahman.
Question: So who am I?
Answer: You are a pope.
Q: What is a pope ?
A: Actually, in the Roman language, influential people and fathers were called popes, but now pope refers to those who take advantage [make use] of others by duping them with tricks and deceits.20
Dayanand, having accurately summarized the etymology of popery (if not pope itself), goes on to offer a quasi-anthropological description of priestly fraud in Europe.
His sums up this corrupt condition with the single pivotal phrase pope-lila.
Under the regime of pope-lila, Roman popes would rob their disciples (chelas) of all their rupees by selling them indulgences (hu*-$). The pope-ji would lay the paper contract in front of an image (m+rti) of Jesus or Mary, and then instruct the devotee to carry it with him to the grave, so that he could hand it to the angel who comes to bring him to heaven. There, the pope said, the paper would purchase celestial amenities, such as a house, a garden, servants, food, drink, and clothing. The suggested donation for this magical paper is 100,000 rupees. As Dayanand explains, this regime of pope-lila prevailed in Europe as long as ignorance prevailed.21 With the spread of knowledge (vidy!), however, deceit (j+)h$ l$l!) became less pervasive; even so, it has not yet been rooted out (231-232).
Having painted this scene, Dayanand goes on to establish his critical comparison
between Europe and India. He does this glibly, with a confident claim to pure
20 In Hindi, the dialogue is as follows:
pra.an: to ham kaun hai#?
uttar: tum pop ho. P: pop kisko kahete hai#?
U: asal isk$ r+man bh!(! me# to ba/! aur pit! k! n!m pop hai, parantu ab chal-kapa) se d+sre ko )hag kar apn! proyojan s!dhanew!le ko pop kahete hai# (SP, 231).
21 jab tak y+rop me# m+rkht! th$, tab tak vah!# popl$l! calt$ th$ (SP, 231-232).
equivalence ( Just like this [vaise h$]). Dayanand s description of Indian popery echoes many of the claims made by James Mill and other apologists of empire. He fulminates against the harsh (ka/!) system of rules that the priests had established in India, such that a person could no longer do anything without a pope s command (popo# k$ !gy!).
By Dayananad s account (as by Mill s), there is no outside to the regime of popish rule.
The priests have captured all of India with their verbal traps (vacan-j!l) and illusions
(mithy!), with rumor (gap), trickery and deceit (chal-kapa)). Under their guidance, dark tradition (andhaparampar!) overtook the world, and all humanity came under their sway (va.). Dayanand s description is dominated by imagery of hierarchy and abasement: the worship of the pope s feet (cara*o# k$ p+j!), and shepherd gurus (ga/iye ke sam!n j+)he gur+) using their pope-lila to control their herds and extort their for milk (SP, 232).
Even while asserting the equivalence of European and Indian popery, however, Dayanand also introduces points of critical difference. Two are immediately apparent in this introductory passage. First, Dayanand refits the world history of fraud to a Hindu chronology: the great war narrated in the epic Mahabharata ushered in the current corrupt era. Although the first sprout (a#kur) of wickedness may have preceded those tragic events, it was only after the massacre at Kur+k(etra that this sprout was able to grow into a tree (v/k(). In the spiritual vacuum produced by the epochal battle, false gurus and brahmans were able to assume the roles of the ancient rishis. Second, in order to conceptualize his comparative task, Dayanand deploys the notion of the avatar, (literally, a descending or coming down; more generally, the incarnation of a deity in human form). The popes have spread deceit in India by taking on countless such avatars.[331]
In both cases, a comparison with William Howitt s Popular History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (1833) is instructive. Where Howitt faults the Flood for opening the profane era of priestly imposture, Dayanand faults Kur+k(etra. Where Howitt uses the figure of the hydra to conceptualize how the discrete manifestations of priestcraft stem from a single source, Dayanand uses the figure of the avatar. Howitt and Dayanand are engaged in strikingly parallel projects: primal traumas set the present at an irrecoverable remove from a sacred golden age; in the present age, a quasitranscendent corruption tyrannizes the world through its local manifestations. The primary difference is one of vocabulary and imagery: the hydra s heads become the
Pope-ji s avatars, without altering their basic conceptual structure. Howitt s and
Dayanand s histories of priestcraft are, in an important sense, the same.
But by transporting popery into a novel context, Dayanand does more than simply echo the Empire s choicest epithet for demonizing Hinduism. Rather, he transposes that epithet into a different constellation of terms and a different cultural imaginary. The ultimate effect of this appropriation and transposition of popery is to reterritorialize both this word and the polemical, anticlerical modernity of which it is a signal part. Dayanand insists that the roots of religious modernity secularism s prehistory, to use Gauri Viswanathan s phrase are to be found in ancient India as much as in early modern Britain.[332] In his hands, popery becomes something more than a merely imperial idiom; he makes it sets down multiple roots and gestures toward multiple, off-secular modernities.
The imposture theory would have appealed to Dayanand for several reasons. First, it dovetailed with his interest in science and technology: religious frauds provided Dayanand with an opportunity to fantasize about priests theatrical and technical accomplishments.[333] At Somn!th, for instance, massive magnets suspended the temple in mid-air (until invading Muslims ruined this proto-scientific special effect) (SP, 266-267). At K!liy!kant, equally ingenious priests engineered a statue to smoke a hookah. The m+rti s mouth was fitted with a tube that led to a secret room behind the sanctum sanctorum; there, a hidden man ( p$chew!l! !dm$ ) blew his hookah smoke back into the temple proper (265-66). At Puri, the priests equipped the Lord Jaggan!th s chariot with a mechanical apparatus that propelled it forward, as if by magic (263-265). Where a skeptic earlier in the century had found only laborers, Dayanand found a technological wonder.[334] Although he denounced the miracle as a fraud, he seems impressed nonetheless with its technical wizardry. As elsewhere, charlatanic special effects fuel the techno-scientific imagination.[335]
Second, the imposture theory provided Dayanand with a foreign vocabulary that had clear tactical use value. Dayanand s hybrid attack on his Hindu nemeses heightens the stakes of heterodoxy by refracting it through the discourses of the nation. If a brahman is not properly Hindu, he is also not properly Indian (or, to use Dayanand s term, Aryan). Instead, he is a pope, an avatar of a global type obviously affiliated with the Christian West. Dayanand s use of avatar here is slightly peculiar: these popes descend not vertically, from on high, but laterally, from the West. Where British writers depicted the crafty priest as quintessentially Indian, Dayanand does just the opposite. The pope can be named only in English, and his pious fraud points emphatically toward the British Isles. To insist that a brahman is not a brahman, but rather a pope, is to effect a semantic exile. This is a forced conversion of sorts, a rhetorical excommunication. Dayanand stakes his claim to Hindu orthodoxy by expatriating his Puranic, Tantric, and Vedantic opponents. In the Saty"rth Prak"sh, to be heterodox is to be a resident alien, and to be a charlatan is to be both.[336]
Dayanand positioned his recalibrated Hinduism as the religion of the Aryan nation,[337] and he did so by writing a thorough history of religious error in India. In many
ways, Dayanand s history simulates the natural history of religion genre that was so central to the English Enlightenment.[338] Like those narratives, its world historical tale unfolds from a moment of traumatic rupture that sunders the present from the lost plenitude of divine truth (here, the great war of the Mahabharata). Like those narratives, it makes use of a fourfold taxonomy to classify the world s religions.[339] According to Dayanand, anti-Vedic religions (vedviruddh mat) falls into four categories: Pur!*$, Jain$, Kir!n$, and Kur!n$ (i.e. Puranic Hinduism, Jainism,
Christianity, and Islam). The thousand other false religions all stem from one of these four branches (sh!kh!), each of them refuted in one of the Saty"rth Prak"sh s final four chapters (SP, 226).
In a sense, Dayanand s history founds the nation on a lie. Truth precedes history proper and persists in the present only as trace, as something in need of retrieval. The actual history of the nation, especially of the religious nation, can only be told as a history of errors. Gyan Prakash has argued a similar point. By founding the modern Indian nation in a lost Vedic past, Dayanand splits the nation from the inside. The revenant classical moment erupts into the present. It functions as an anteriority, not as an origin, in that it interrupts the homogenous, empty time of the nation with an archaic temporality; it disrupts the organicist pretension that the nation evolves continuously from its point of origin.[340] As the contemporary national self emerges in the differential sign of the return, as its time is expressed in the repetition of another time, an alienating otherness becomes the medium of expressing the fullness of the nation. The nation becomes strange unto itself, as a searing sense of loss inscribes it with a constitutive lack, a trace of inadequacy that leads ineluctably to the prior presence of the Vedic era.[341] Dayanand may promise a future time when the plentitude of primordial truth will be restored; but, in this book, he can deliver only the mythos of the lost golden age.
The story begins before five thousand years ago, when there was no religion (mat) other than the Vedic religion (vedmat). A seed of ignorance that had been planted in this golden age came to fruit on the battlefield of Kur+k(etra, which turned wisdom (buddh$) upside down (+l)$) (226-230). In the new dark age, ignorant gurus spread tricks, deceits, and irreligion. False brahmans, thinking only of their livelihood, proclaimed themselves deities to be worshipped. Members of the others castes, without any access to Sanskritic knowledge, accepted whatever rumor (gap) was put before them as the truth. Helplessly enchanted (va.$bh+t), they came to belong to these false brahmans. Wisdom was hooked to delusion (buddh$ bhramyukt), and imagination replaced truth; people came to spread whatever religion happened to come into their minds.
At this earliest stage of history, India still ruled the world. From the Creation until the Great War of the Mahabharat, the world-kings (s!rvabhaum cakravart$) all hailed from the clan of Aryans. Sanskrit was the great scientific language, and the unparalleled wealth of Arya-vart was the envy of all. The imperial echo in such claims is sometimes eerie. When Dayanand asks who would next establish a kingdom crossing continents, his ambition becomes clear: Vedic India anticipates British India. It is no coincidence that in this passage Dayanand specifically repudiates the ability of Europeans like Max M ller to interpret the ancient texts properly. Here Dayanand inscribes even the fulsome Vedic Age with a lack. The Vedic nation not only splits the modern Indian nation; it is itself split by an anachronism in that it is made to carry the trace of the British Empire.
Dayanand narrates the rupture between the lost Vedic past and the modern Indian nation as a fall from truth. The nation proper is born of a lie, conjured by the clever ruses of crafty popes determined to quash Vedic piety. The history of the Hindu nation turns into a catalogue of these lies, a survey of pope-lila. Truth, the fundamentally prehistoric province of the Vedas, continues to erupt within this history of error. Indeed, it drives history in an almost dialectic manner: the popes devise newer, cleverer ruses to subsume the criticisms of their neo-Vedic opponents, and the consequent elaboration of their popery propels the fraught history of India. Truth then (Dayanand s titular satya ) serves as the differential sign of return that inscribes the nation with searing lack and alienating otherness. But this truth as absence, as the deferred is also, above all, productive: it spurs on the proliferating lies that drive history.
The perennial opponent of the popes is the Man of Truth (the satpur+(), who in his saintly avatars has resisted dark tradition through the ages. A telescoped history of this perennial conflict follows. In those first dark years, the popes devised the W!m M!rg, the orgiastic left-handed path of Tantra. The first great critic was soon to follow. The king of Gorakhpur had been pressured by the popes to have his beloved queen attempt intercourse with a horse (sam!gram gho/e se). She died in the process. The disillusioned monarch gave the kingdom to his son and became a sadhu determined to expose the pretensions of the popes (popo# k$ pol nikalne lag!). His efforts produced the materialistic C!rv!ka sect, and when the sect spread, the popes took notice.
They devised Jainism to co-opt the C!rv!ka critique. The new religion claimed critique for pope-lila by turning its sarcasm against the Vedas themselves. Still more devastatingly, the Jain popes invented an entirely new form of devotion: m+rti p+j!, the worship of stone images. Statues of the Jain tirthankars soon displaced the transcendent God in the public s imagination. The period of Jain rule over Aryavarta their Raj extended from about 2800 years ago until about 2500 years ago (SP, 236237). Then, about 2200 years ago, Lord Shankara stepped forward to restore the Vedic religion and bring an end to Jain corruption. Shankara is central to the Saty"rth Prak"sh and will be discussed in greater depth below. Here suffice it to say that, after his death, his critique too was subsumed by the grand system of religious fraud. This was in part because of his questionable philosophical claims (non-dualism, Dayanand tells us, is a delusion). But it owed more to the perennial cleverness of the popes, who claimed that Shankara was an incarnation of Shiva. It was about 1900 years ago that, under King Vikramaditya, the Shaivas and Wam Margis gained in influence and tried to collapse all duty, work, and desire into the worship of the lingam.
Around this time, the Purani religion was consolidated. In order to compete with the Jains, the Purani popes fabricated the eighteen Puranas, came up with twentyfour avatars (counterparts to the twenty-four Jain tirthankars), and proliferated temples, images, and stories (SP, 249). Dayanand built his career castigating Puranic Hinduism for its excesses, and his discussion here is no exception. He claims that all of the Pur"!as were composed by unlearned Purani popes, who forged the names of dead authors like Vy!sa; lest doubt remain as to his textual targets, he enumerates them.
These scriptures should, he quips, be called Nav$*as (New Texts) rather than Puranas (Old Texts).[342] In addition to faking their scriptures, the Purani popes also took up the image-worship of the Jains and rendered it a general practice. Visual devotion has rendered millions of people in Aryavart useless, beggarly, and lazy and has spread foolishness and lies across the entire world (262).
Dayanand concludes his history of Indian religions with quick jabs at early modern religious movements, including the followers of Guru Nanak (1469-1539) and Kabir (1440-1518).[343] The sternest critique, however, is reserved for the Pu()im!rg (the movement founded Sri Vallabhac!rya [1479-1531] that is discussed at length in Chapter 3 of this dissertation). According to Dayanand, all the majesty of the Vallabhac!rya Maharajas derives from their trickery (chal-prapa c) and fraud (dh+rt!). He assures his reader that the sect rested on a lie from the very first (Lak(ma*bha)), Vallabha s father, was an illusionist [mithy!v!d$], and his lie [lila] was taken up by his son).[344] Dayanand consistently uses the word lila when describing the misdeeds of the Vallabhacaryas, and he opposes Vallabha lila to the Vedas and the Shastras. The Gosains use a net of illusion to trap the hapless and convince them of their sovereignty.[345]
Dayanand s diatribe against the Pu()im!rg recycles many of the same complaints made in the 1862 trial of the Maharaj Libel Case. It harps on the trio of offerings that the gurus allegedly demanded of their devotees ( tan, man, dhan ; that is, body, mind, and wealth). It mentions those same devotees drinking the water that the guru used to wash his feet and his dhoti (SP, 306-7).[346] It even discusses the venereal diseases to which the sect s leaders were allegedly prone.[347] Rather sensationally, Dayanand allows himself to speculate about the theology of such infections: if Krishna s human incarnations have contracted a disease, then Krishna must have contracted it too. Dayanand knows he is being mischievous here, and he adds a killjoy moral maxim for good measure: where there is bhog (enjoyment), there is also rog (disease) (306307). In short, Dayanand is never more himself than when he caustically congratulates the Pu()im!rg: Bravo, sir, bravo! What a good religion it is! [348]
Dayanand s whirlwind history of Hinduism raises several critical questions about the relation of religion to the Indian nation. First, it suggests that even an effort to debunk Hinduism can reinforce Hindu hegemony. Dayanand was committed to
Hindu theism; but even had he been a radical atheist, his skeptical procedure would have borne the impress of the religion that produced it. Dayanand remaps the subcontinent s miraculous Hindu terrain as a geography of fraud. Popish illusion sweeps up Kashi, Gaya, Calcutta, Puri, Rameshwar, K!liy!kant, Dwarka, Somnath,
Punjab s Jwala-Mukhi, Amritsar, Haridwar, and Mathura (262-269). In debunking these
Hindu miracles, Dayanand reinforces this geography s fundamental Hindu-ness: it is
Hindu sites and Hindu sites only that must be reformed in order to redeem the nation.
Muslims enter Dayanand s history only to destroy the popes ruses. For instance, when Mahmud of Ghazni attacks Somnath, his army destroys the temple s miracle magnet, discovers the cache of jewels hidden in the idol, and whips and enslaves the popes. However ambivalently, Dayanand does align himself with Mahmud s iconoclasm. The overall project of the Saty"rth Prak"sh, however, is to take such non-Hindu critical positions and enfold them within a criticism position marked by Vedic reform.
According to Gyan Prakash, Dayanand articulated his Vedic nation not only through a constitutive temporal fissure (the rupture with the past), but also through a synchronic social fissure. Prakash argues that Puranic Hinduism is inscribed within the field of neo-Vedic discourse as a subaltern mode of religiosity, and he means this in a precise sense. The subaltern functions internally to the system of dominance as that which signifies the limit to that system. To conceive of the subaltern as a pure externality is to collude with dominant knowledge systems, which rely on just such a myth of unknowable externality in order produce their own inevitable hegemony. The figure of the peasant serves as Prakash s example. Although dominant knowledge systems have depicted the superstitious peasant as the absolute outside to modern rationality, knowledge of which is not accessible, such systems always already recognize and know the peasant precisely as the figure of unreason and incomprehensibility.[349]
This formulation, of course, does not address the question of how the peasant, as ideological figure, determines what sorts of political utterance are available to actual subaltern individuals or whether one might make ever make empirical claims about actual subalterns without reinforcing the very discursive structures that bring groups into political being precisely as subaltern. Prakash finesses this question by suggesting that the subaltern, as ideological function, does provide a space in which traces of that which is external to systems of dominance can surface within the dominant discourse: subalernity erupts from within the system of dominance and marks its limit from within, that its externality to dominant systems of knowledge and power surface inside the system of dominance, but only as an intimation, as a trace of that which eludes the dominant discourse (SP, 288). Subalternity can be known either as a function of dominance or as a trace of that which eludes dominance, but not as a full presence that stands beyond the dominant discourse. Indeed, it is the fragmentary nature of subalternity and its refusal of wholeness that provides the most potent critique of the totality of dominant discourse.
Prakash suggests that Puranic Hinduism occupies just such a subaltern position within Dayanand s Vedic modernity. Puranic devotion and, I would add, pope-lila acts as a subaltern otherness that, while allegedly unintelligible as a category of knowledge and belief, is nonetheless completely knowable as superstition. Because Puranic Hinduism exists within Vedic discourse and is, indeed, constitutive of that discourse, it cannot be extinguished Dayanand s reform project is thus an impossible project. It fumbles over its inability to extinguish the self-exteriority of magic and superstition. True religion is thus forced into self-alienation at the very moment that it produces itself as true (SP, 292-93).
One might amplify Prakash s claim about the subaltern position of Puranic religion in the Saty"rth Prak"sh and later Arya Samaj writings by referring to Dayanand s biography. If Puranic religion was subaltern for Dayanand in the abstract sense developed by Prakash, it was also subaltern to him in another sense: it would have been redolent of caste groups that stood below his family in the social hierarchy of Kathiawar. Dayanand s reformism might well be read, rather than as a program of simple caste uplift, as an attempt to brahmanize his social others.
J. T. H. Jordans has argued that Dayanand s early Kathiawari background had a profound influence on his later life, much like the influence it had on later Kathiawari reformer M. K. Gandhi both, for instance, were likely inspired in their rigorous vegetarianism by the region s Jain ethos, and Dayanand s iconoclasm may have been inspired by that of the Sth!nakav!s$ Jains. Practices prevalent in the region, like the shraadha ceremony, would later become the primary objects of Dayanand s reformist scorn.[350] Jordans argues that young Dayanand (whose pre-initiatory name we do not know) would have been very aware of his minority status as a Shaiva brahman.[351] Brahmans composed only seven percent of Kathiawar s total Hindu population, and most of them were Shaivas, who would have prided themselves on their spiritual descent from "a#kar!c!rya and their preservation of the Vedic rites.
The differences in ritual practices between the Shaiva Smarta brahmans and other caste groups, who were largely Vai(*ava and Jain, would have underscored the caste division. Although young Dayanand s family was very observant and emphasized their religious heritage, other brahmans probably did not. Fallen brahmans would have associated with the Vai(*avas of other castes and would have been very visible to young Dayanand.[352] His later efforts to eliminate these practices and replace them with orthodox Vedic worship can easily be read as an effort to reclaim the fallen brahmans and eliminate the caste cultures that had corrupted them. The rhetorical production of Puranic Hinduism as heterodox or subaltern thus has clear stakes in terms of caste hierarchy, with caste at the all-India level made to enact a drama scripted in Kathiawar.
In order to persuasively depict his neo-Vedic orthodoxy as possessing a universal appeal, Dayanand has to expand it beyond the bounds of the brahmans. I will argue that a key method by which is does this is through the formal device of the dialogue. By shifting from history to this more fictive and literary mode, Dayanand imagines the subjectivities of his social others and appropriates their imagined voices to his own agenda.
One dialogue in particular suggests how Dayanand sought to co-opt subaltern voices for Vedic modernity. Once, there was a Jat (ek j!) th!). This opening phrase signals the stylistic shift to a fable about a Jat, a member of a farming caste from northwestern India (SP, 282-4). Once there was a Jat who had a cow who gave copious quantities of delicious (sv!di()) milk. Every once in a while, the local Pope-ji would get a taste of this milk, and as the family priest (purohit), he plotted that when the Jat s old father died, he would take the cow as a ritual gift (sa2kalp). When the father s time arrived, the Pope-ji came and demanded that the Jat give a cow in the name of his father ( iske h!th se god!n kar!o ). The Jat got out ten rupees, put it in his father s hand, and told the pope to pronounce the benediction. The pope demurred, insisting that a father dies only once: the Jat should fetch a young milk-giving cow of the best
sort.
Here Dayanand s narration begins to give way to a dialogue, perhaps the most characteristic formal device of the Saty"rth Prak"sh as a whole. This is to be a verbal contest between the Jat and the Pope-ji. The Jat protests that he has only one cow with which to support his family, and he offers the Pope twenty rupees to buy himself a cow. The Pope scorns him ( v!hj$ v!h!), suggesting that he values a cow more highly than his father. He then marshals the support of the Jat s family, whom he had duped previously and now controls at a signal (un sabko pahile h$ se popj$ ne bahek! rakkh! th! aur us samay bh$ ish!r! kar diy!). Under pressure, the Jat gives the cow to the Pope, who takes it home before returning to perform the funerary rites and other pope-lila.
Thenceforward, the Jat goes from house to house begging milk in order to care for his children. In the morning of the fourteenth day, he comes to the Pope-ji s house where he finds the Pope filling the milk-jug (ba)lo$) from the cow. The Pope invites the Jat in (!iye bai)hiye) and tells him that he will put the milk away and be right back (duddh dhar !u#). The Jat demands, and rather impolitely, that the Pope bring the milk-jug with him (popj$ j!, ba)lo$ s!mne dhar, bai)he).
Jat-ji: You are a big liar.
Pope-ji: What lie have I committed?
Jat-ji: Why did you take the cow?
Pope-ji: To help your father cross the river of death.
Jat-ji: Then why didn t you send it to death s riverbank? I trusted you. Who knows how deep my father must have drowned in the river of death.
Pope-ji: No, no. As an effect of the merit of this gift, a second cow has appeared there, and it carried your father across.
Jat-ji: How far is the river of death from here, and in which direction?
Pope-ji: Probably about thirty thousand miles (t$s kro/ ko. d+r) Jat-ji: Show me the letter or telegram with the news that the second cow appeared and carried my father across.
Pope-ji: Aside from the writings of the Gar$&a Pur"!a, I have no letter or telegram.
Jat-ji: How can I accept the Gar$&a Pur"!a as true?
Pope-ji: Just like everyone does.
Jat-ji: Your fathers made this book for your livelihood. Nothing is dearer to a father than his son. When my father sends me a letter or a telegram, then I will send the cow to death s riverbank so that it carries him across; afterwards, I will bring the cow back to my house, so that I can feed the milk to my children and myself.
The Jat takes the cow and its accoutrements and goes home. The Pope scolds him for taking his gift back and threatens him with ruin, but the Jat tells him to shut up (ch+p raho!). Dayanand glosses the moral of the story thusly: When men are like this Jat, then Pope-lila will not exist in the world. [353]
This is a striking fable of class uplift through critical inquiry. The Jat, an uneducated peasant, sees through the ideological ruses cast by the Pope, and, having shed his false consciousness, takes back his rightful property. Newly enlightened, he can lead his duped relatives and, Dayanand suggests, all of humanity towards a future free of priestly manipulation. In the process, he attains a status deserving of respect early on in the story, Dayanand switches from referring to him merely as Jat to referring to him as Jat-ji. This appellation may well be ironic, especially in light of the Jat s comic ignorance ( have you received a telegram from the underworld? ); even so, the story holds the lowly Jat up among the ranks of the Men of Truth.
The Jat thus becomes Dayanand s subaltern mouthpiece. In this, he is not alone: throughout the Saty"rth Prak"sh, and particularly in its dialogues, Dayanand writes in voices other than his own so that he can claim these others for his Vedic revival. The real subalterns, Dayanand suggests, are the religious subalterns. Those marginalized because of their caste or class can join the dominant discourse and speak in the voice of the Vedas. While reform Hindu agendas like Dayanand s did open up very real opportunities for caste and class mobility, they also foreclosed certain possibilities in the process. As Jordens suggests in his analysis of Dayanand s biography, this reform program stipulated that in order to speak the subaltern had to adopt the lifestyle of a
Shaiva brahman.
I would argue, however, that traces of subjective positions other than
Dayanand s are to be found throughout the Saty"rth Prak"sh in fables just like this one. Dayanand clearly extracted stories from networks of oral exchange to include them in his book (indeed, much of the learned Sanskritic material as well had only recently entered print circulation). Some of this material seems to put itself in quotation marks against the will of its compiler, resisting his effort to conflate all skeptical positions into his neo-Vedic reform program. Indeed, it would be possible to write Dayanand s text into a very different kind of history, one in which it plays a subordinate role as a stopping point in the larger life of one of these stories. In such a history, the folktale would subsume the reformist tract, rather than vice versa.
In this vein, I can offer a partial account of one of the Saty"rth Prak"sh s stories.
Dayanand writes of a thief who was punished for his crime by having his nose cut off. Much to everyone s surprise, the noseless man started to dance, laugh, and sing. When people asked why he was so happy, he explained that, with no nose, he could now see the Lord Narayan. The thief grew famous as a great sage, and he started to draw disciples. One of these disciples decided to cut off his own nose so that he too could see the Lord. When he did, the thief leaned in and whispered: You do just as I do, or else we will both be ridiculed. [354] Soon a full sect of nose-cutters formed, and news of them spread to the king. But before the monarch chopped off his nose too, a wise old minister intervened. Reasoning that he had very few years left anyway, he cut his own nose off first. When the thief leaned in to tell the minister to join the cheat, he exposed the whole movement, and the king had them all arrested. As Dayanand glosses the tale:
All the trickery of the anti-Vedic religious lineages is just like this. [355]
A version of the same story had previously been recorded in November 1817 by the Rev. William Bowley. This version takes place at Juggernaut, where a blind main feigned to see Krishna. A deluded multitude gathered and fed the huckster a daily diet of dainties. Soon he drew a disciple, who blinded himself and was rewarded only with harsh words from his guru: Thou fool! What dost thou wish to see? Is it not enough that we are supplied with every thing that is delicious? Hold your peace. These two charlatans fed off the crowd until a more cunning disciple came along, blinding himself in only one eye. The guru, not knowing the cheat, told him the secret. The one-eyed man then proceeded to chastise the imposter and exposed him to the people. Bowley glossed the tale thus: each of the Hindoo sects knows its own fraud, but is ashamed to divulge it. [356]
Other versions of the tale were collected in the decades after the publication of the Saty"rth Prak"sh. These include a Tamil version collected by E. J. Robinson in 1885; a version included in the 1894 North Indian Notes and Queries; and a version in Pandit Ganga Datt Upreti s 1894 collection of tales from Garhwal.48 Most recently, anthropologist Kirin Narayan was told the same story in 1983 by a man in Nasik who recalled having read it as a child in the Saty"rth Prak"sh. This teller, Swamiji, nimbly adapted the written tale for an oral context, combining it with Dayanand s frame story and pulling listeners in by pretending to cut their noses and by getting them to dance. Swamiji presented the story as a critique of transnational guru culture, with its many famous frauds; although, as Narayan demonstrates, several listeners walked away with divergent interpretations.49
I have not been able to trace similar trajectories for other stories included in the Saty"rth Prak"sh, but it is worth asking how Dayanand tried to position his book within an oral as well as a print public. For instance, he peppers the text with sayings (kathan) that seem to invite oral repetition. Examples of these include blind of eye and full of purse (!nkh ke andhe aur g!n)h ke p+re) and whether you live or die, fill the pope s stomach (j$vo v! m!ro popj$ k! pe) bharo) (SP, 288). Suggesting that he meant for these slogans to circulate beyond the text is decidedly speculative, but it does seem plausible, given Dayanand s attunement to overlapping oral publics.
48 E. J. Robinson, Tales and Poems of South India (London: T. Woolmer, 1885), 31-32; North Indian Notes and
Queries IV (1894), no. 30; Pandit Ganga Datt Upreti, Proverbs and Folklore of Kumaun and Garhwal (Lodiana: Lodiana Mission Press, 1894), 50-51. All cited by Kirin Narayan, Storytellers, Saints, and Scoundrels: Folk Narrative in Hindu Religious Teaching (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1989), 142-143.
Narayan identifies this as tale type No. 1701, The Noseless Man, in Stith Thompson and Warren E.
Roberts, Types of Indic Oral Tales: India, Pakistan, and Ceylon (Helsinki: Suomalainen Tiedeakatemia, 1960).
49 Narayan, Storytellers, 132-159.
In the Saty"rth Prak"sh, Dayanand tries to construct a distinctively Indian skeptical tradition by co-opting several differently positioned voices. While the Jat is an important conquest for this project, he cannot compare with Shankara (c.788-820), the great founder of the philosophical school of Advaita Ved!nta. For Dayanand, Shankara is the paradigmatic Man of Truth and the most iconic enemy of illusion. However, Dayanand s ultimate agenda is very different from Shankara s. Where Shankara sought to dissolve the perceptual world into its otherworldly ontological ground, Dayanand remained committed to the empirical reality of this world. Thus, in order to insinuate himself into Shankara s skeptical lineage, Dayanand has to claim Shankara away from non-dualism. As a consequence, in the Saty"rth Prak"sh, Ved!nta serves as both the idiom and the object of critique.
Dayanand has two major techniques for upending Ved!nta. First, he collapses metaphysics into rhetoric, arguing that Shankara did not believe his own ontological claims but rather espoused them tactically to undermine the false religions of his enemies. Second, Dayanand appropriates Vedantic idioms of illusion and tethers them to worldly ends. In his hands, maya loses its status as overarching cosmic principle and comes to indicate merely human fraud. The hybrid conjunct pope-lila performs this work in miniature. While it amplifies its component parts by widening the resonance of each, it also quite tendentiously redefines lila. As Dayanand makes clear, trickery is never divine, and maya is to be understood as fraud, pure and simple.
Shankara is arguably the most famous philosopher in the Indian tradition, and what he is most famous for is his espousal of a strict non-dualism. Despite his own dualistic commitments, Dayanand likely felt the need to reckon with Shankara due to his training in Vedantic thought. [357] The extensive body of writings attributed to the great sage, such as his influential commentaries on the Upani%ads, the Brahma S$tra, and the Bhagavad G(t", insists that this world s plurality of beings is an illusion. In order to achieve liberation from the material world (sa#s!ra), the individual soul (j$va) must realize its fundamental unity with Brahman, the one Being that subsumes all others. Shankara was at particular pains to explain that because Brahman exceeds the descriptive capacities of the human mind, it should be understood as formless or
without qualities (nirgu*a).
Shankara, without entirely denying the reality of the material world (jagat), did nonetheless present it as an illusion. The standard metaphor is that of the serpent in the rope. Just as an ignorant (avidy!) person immersed in darkness might mistake a coiled rope for a snake, the ignorant soul (j$va) misapprehends Brahman.[358] Like the serpent, the material world is thus but an appearance (vivarta) of Brahman and does not exist in its own right. As Dayanand puts it, the false is that which appears, but does not exist (jo vastu na ho aur prat$t hove). The creative force whereby Brahman gives rise to the illusion of the world is known as m!y!. This force inheres in the ignorant soul rather than in Brahman, and it falls away as soon as the soul sheds its ignorance.52 Dayanand pithily distills Shankara s non-dualistic doctrine thusly: The ultimate being is true, the world illusion, and the soul one with the ultimate being (brahm satya, jagat mithy!, aur j$v brahm ki ekt!) (SP, 239).
While Dayanand s text does recycle substantial portions of Shankara s Advaitin vocabulary, it does not intervene extensively within Shankara s argument. Dayanand does manage several retorts to the Vedantins whom he writes into dialogues. For instance, he objects strenuously to the claim that something can appear without first existing.53 It is completely impossible for that which does not exist to be represented, just as it is impossible for there to be a reflection of a barren woman s son.54 After making these arguments, however, Dayanand somewhat surprisingly announces his victory by proclaiming the following principle: only when a philosophical position is indestructible (akha*-aniya) is it acceptable (m!nniya). That is, because Dayanand can mount cogent objection to the Vedantin s ontological claims, those claims must be false (239-243). By placing the burden of proof on the Vedantin, Dayanand saves himself from having to outthink Shankara. In fact, it seems fair to say that Dayanand is
52 For Sankara, see the following: Advaita Vedanta up the Samkara and his Pupils , ed. Karl H. Potter, vol. 3 of Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies (Delhi, 1981); A Thousand Teachings: The Upadeshasaahasrii of Shankara, trans. Mayeda Sengaku (Tokyo, 1979); The Vedanta Sutra, with the Commentary by Sankara, trans. George Thibault, Sacred Books of the East (New York, 1962); Jonathan Bader, Conquest of the Four Quarters: Traditional Accounts of the Life of Sankara (New Delhi, 2000); N. V. Iseva, Shankara and Indian Philosophy (Albany, 1993);
Roger Marcaurelle, Freedom through Inner Renunciation: Sankara s Philosophy in a New Light (Albany, 2000);
George P. Victor, Life and Teachings of Adi Sankaracarya (New Delhi, 2002); Eliot Deutsch, Advaita Vedanta: A Philosophical Reconstruction (Honolulu, 1969); Arvind Sharma, The Rope and the Snake: A Metaphorical Exploration of Advaita Vedanta (New Delhi, 1997).
53 jo vastu h$ nah$#, usk$ prat$ti kaise ho sakt$ hai? (SP, 239).
54 kyo#ki jo vastu nah$#, usk! bh!sm!n hon! sarvath! asambhav hai, jais! bandhy! ke putr k!
pratibimb kabh$ nah$# ho sakt! (SP, 243)
considerably less interested in metaphysical niceties than he is in philosophy s worldly effects. He clearly disapproves of the ethos of modern day Vedantins, whom he depicts in the Saty"rth Prak"sh as idlers, their unkempt hair a testament to their dubious moral constitution.[359] If the purpose of religion is to develop character, Ved!nta has, in Dayanand s view, clearly failed.
Dayanand extricates Shankara from Advaita by turning the great sage s metaphysics into a polemical tactic: the philosopher only adopted the non-dualist thesis to refute the anti-Vedic religion of the Jains.[360] By Dayanand s account, Shankara s career centered on public debates (.!str!rth), rather than on philosophical reflection. The axial event in Shankara s life was a debate held at Ujjain, where his ace argumentation convinced the local king and several neighboring monarchs to return to the Vedic fold.[361] Afterwards, Shankara roamed India criticizing the Jains and praising the Vedas, until the fateful day when he was poisoned by his enemies.[362] Baldly put, Dayanand turns Shankara s career into a premonition of his own and, in doing so, asserts the supremacy of rhetoric over metaphysics. In the Saty"rth Prak"sh, the agonistic arena of debate overwhelms all else.
The overriding concern with the powers of speech is evident throughout the text. Dayanand chastises Vedantins, for their tendency to babble.[363] He tells mothers how instruct their children in correct pronunciation and socially appropriate modes of address, as well as in essential mantras, shlokas, and sutras. Rhetorical discipline, he writes, will protect the child from the lures of the charlatan (dh+rt) (32). Dayanand reinforces his pedagogical program with a series of maxims and moral teachings about the central place that right speech should hold in a system of ethics. Speech is the root of all right action, and to lie is to steal from speech.[364] Because truth speaking is first among the virtues, there is no one as base as a liar.[365] One knows the true renunciant (sanny!s$) because he speaks truth ceaselessly (nirantar satya h$ bole) (108). Speech is to be closely regulated and without excess.
As I have suggested, a glowing instance of Dayanand s verbal economy is to be found in the compound pope-lila. This creative adaptation of priestcraft redefines the scope of Advaitin illusion by yoking it to a decidedly different imaginary of deception. Where the first emphasizes human frauds, the second suggests more metaphysical modes of deceit. The overall work done by the conjunction of the two words pope and lila is to assert the primacy of human deception over cosmological deception. Dayanand makes this project explicit in a dialogue that treats the creation of the world. His interlocutor, addressed sarcastically as Pope-ji, claims that Vishnu created the world through the power of his maya. Dayanand, however, will have none of it. God (parame.war) could not have made the world through the purposeless power of his maya,[366] because maya inheres in men (manu(ya) only. Here the divine power of cosmic illusion is equated with more commonplace forms of trickery (chal-kapa)). To be an illusionist (m!y!v$) is to be a cheat; since God is no cheat, He cannot be called an illusionist.[367] However, illusion can exist among men, who are tricky and deceitful; it is precisely these men who are to be called illusionists. [368] The Pope-ji is a case in point: all of his obscurantist tales about Vishnu s divine illusions are themselves nothing but a fraud (dhoka), devised to distract from true religion.
Lila, of course, has a different set of associations than maya. It recalls in particular Krishna s playful dalliance with Radha and the gopis. Dayanand s apparent obsession with this word, and the negative charge with which he invests it, likely derive from the three years that he lived in Mathura, then as now a major center of Krishna devotion and Krishna pilgrimage.[369] During this period, when he was learning to value only texts written by the original rishis, Krishna s lila came to stand in for all modern forms of Hindu devotion. He was especially wroth with the more crassly commercial aspects of the pilgrimage industry, which led him to proclaim in the
Saty"rth Prak"sh that Braj was the place where ignorance came to set up house. [370] For Dayanand, the Krishna country was the epicenter of pope-lila. Not coincidentally, the years that Dayanand spent at Mathura (1860-1863) were also the same years that
Krishna s lila came under national scrutiny due to the notoriety of the Maharaj Libel Case then under trial in Bombay. As J rgen L tt has suggested, the famous trial most likely influenced the budding student of Sanskrit grammar, shaping his later distaste for all things lila. [371]
The overriding objective of the Saty"rth Prak"sh is to undo the regime of lila.
Where lila implies playful confusion of being and appearance (one might think of Krishna s mother Yashoda opening her young son s mouth and, much to her surprise, getting a glimpse of the entire universe), Dayanand has no patience for things that are not what they seem. Religious hypocrites are threatening because they flout the correspondence between seeming and being: they are like cats that crouch before springing to kill, or herons that stand meditatively while hunting. Dayanand aims to expose their dissemblance, to bring appearance (prat$ti) into alignment with reality (vastu). While the shape of his skepticism owes something to Ved!nta, his determined empiricism does not. Where Shankara sought to lift the material veil from the formless divine, Dayanand sought to pull the curtain on unscrupulous mortals.
To be sure, Dayanand does lay out a devotional, metaphysical program in the Saty"rth Prak"sh. He is a strident dualist, and his book makes this very clear. Dayanand insists that the individual soul must be different in kind from the ultimate Being
(brahm), because while the soul is little and knows little (it is alp aur alpagya ), God is omnipresent (sarvavy!pak), omniscient (sarvagya), and never wrong (SP, 111). Counter-intuitively, however, it is precisely Dayanand s passionate commitment to transcendent divinity that enables his worldliness and his practical disinterest in matters divine. Dayanand s dualism disenchants the world by relegating God to a separate sphere. Unlike in the Advaitin system, where the things of this world dissipate mistily into ultimate Being, in Dayanand s dualistic system they have ontological weight of their own. Cleared of constitutive illusion and divine mystery, they open themselves to clear apprehension by the knowing subject and to instrumental manipulation by this same masterful agent. Dayanand s dualism was therefore an epistemological precondition for his interest in science, which could not proceed if, as in Vedantic thought, illusion remained the horizon of the real.
As the above discussion has demonstrated, Dayanand conceived of his work as a religious polemicist as central to the disenchantment of India. His book would expose the regime of pope-lila with all its illusions. It too, I would suggest, draws on the critical metaphors of Advaita Ved!nta. In his explication of the serpent and the rope, Dayanand mentions a lamp (d$p) that brings light to the dark corner, revealing the snake for what it is. For Dayanand, his book is this lamp. The Saty"rth Prak"sh offers both the light of truth and light for truth : it rescues the Vedic religion both by detailing its teachings and by shining its critical scrutiny on India s religious delusions. Dayanand conceived of the book as straight talk (siddh b!t) that would build up true religion and tear down falsehood.[372] When the deluded saw it (isko dekhn!), they would come to understand the difference between the two.[373] As he wrote, it is not natural (sahaj) for knowledge (vigy!n) to remain hidden (gupt).
Dayanand defines the task of the Saty"rth Prak"sh s latter chapters as the
critical appraisal of Indian religions. [374] He conceives of this critical appraisal (sam!locana) as different in kind from the work of mere polemicists, who engage in the field of controversialist debate (v!dviv!d). His aim in this book is not to destroy or oppose anyone;[375] rather, he wants only to distinguish (nir3ay karna) between truth and untruth. As he writes, humans are born to determine truth, not to stir controversy.[376]
He comes down hard on what he calls interreligious debate (matmat!ntar viv!d), an activity that, he claims, can produce only falsehood (mithy!) and unwanted fruit (ani()i phal). By condemning interreligious debate, Dayanand indicates that his task transcends the field of controversy. If the matmat!ntar includes all that is immanent to religion, all that is between or within (both antar ) the competing sects (mats), then Dayanand presents his position as that of transcendent critique. He gains his higher ground through the ultimate authority of the Vedas.
Dayanand concludes his history of Indian religions with a story that dramatizes his attempt to rise above the field of interreligious debate. Suppose a king gathered an assembly (sabh!) of representatives from all the religious traditions (samprad!ya). Although all of the assembled could be classed in four categories (Purani, Jaini, Kirani, and Kurani), they would number about a thousand. Suppose then that some curious investigator (jigy!s+) interrogated each of the gathered representatives. He might begin with the Wam-Margi (representative of the left-handed path of Tantra):
Q: Hey, Maharaj! Up to now, I have not chosen a guru or a religion. Tell me!
Whose is the best of all the religions? Which one should I choose?
A: It is ours.
Q: How are the other nine hundred and ninety nine?
A: All are false and lead to hell . There is no religion higher than ours (SP, 317).
Having learned a little about this first false religion, the investigator moves on. The Wam Margi protests ( Yikes! What confusion you have fallen into. Don t go near anyone. Become our disciple. ), but to no avail. The investigator circles the room, questioning a Shaiva, a Vedanti, a Jain, a Christian, a Maulvi, a Vai(*ava, plus sectarians of Kabir, N!nak, D!du, Vallabha, Sahaj!nand, M!dhva, and others. Each claims the unparalleled superiority of his own religion. The form of the story, however, belies this claim: the thousand religions are nothing if not identical in their pretensions to singular truth. The investigator concludes his research more perplexed than when he began it. He overwhelmed by the dissension (viroddh) among the nine hundred ninetynine teachers, and he concludes that none of them is worthy (yogya) of being his guru. They are merely shopkeepers, merchants, and pimps (bha/u!) who praise their own goods (vastu) while insulting those of others (316-318).
The befuddled investigator, however, does not give up. He finds a sage (an !ptvigy!n individual) to whom he confesses his confusion: If I become the disciple of any one of the sampradayas, I will make opponents (viroddh$) of the other nine hundred ninety-nine. Whoever has nine hundred ninety-nine enemies and one friend will never have peace. Please instruct me as to which religion I should follow. The sage informs the seeker that all the sects are born of ignorance and run by tricksters. However, there is a solution. In whatever matter the thousand sects are of one mind, that is to be taken as the Vedic religion. And in whatever matter there is dissension among them, that is be taken as imaginary, false, irreligious, and unacceptable. [377]
Having taken this advice, Dayanand avers that the ekmat (that in which all religions are in agreement) can only be the vedmat (the Vedic religion). In this scenario, the Vedic religion can only be the One Religion if everyone agrees on it.
Within the bounds of this narrative, Dayanand is able to engineer a broad consensus. The investigator (his proxy), steps into the center of the circle (ma*-al$), and from his transcendent vantage point, gets all of the teachers to agree to the tenets of the Vedic religion. Somewhat tautologically, the primary point of agreement is that religion is the stuff of truth, not falsehood.[378] Like a subcontinental Herbert of Cherbury, the Vedic critic locates his set of Common Notions. However, his effort quickly fails. Falsehood is very profitable, and the thousand teachers refuse to sacrifice their livelihoods to the truth. They admit their guilt (as Dayanand puts it, their inner lila comes out [tumh!r$ bh$tar k$ l$l! b!har ! g!$], but they do not convert (320).
Moreover, they mount a cogent argument: there can never be one religion (ekmat) in the world because human virtues, deeds, and natures (gu*-karm-svabh!v) will always be diverse (bhinn-bhinn). This classic formulation enables a certain kind of tolerance. There are many paths to God and Truth, and because individuals differ, each will find a different path appropriate. Dayanand has a ready (and somewhat menacing) answer to this objection. A program of Vedic education will unite these diverse natures and so create a nation wherein it would be possible to impose a single religion (SP, 31920). In other words, the disciplines laid out in the first half of the Saty"rth Prak"sh will remake everyone s corrupted minds, such that their universal application will produce universal agreement (ekmat). Dayanand seeks to exercise a pastoral power over the
Indian population, managing both the bodies and the souls of the nation.
I think it is significant, however, that he cannot or will not imagine a triumphant Vedic truth. Even in his fantasy assembly of all religions, the popes continue to resist him. In the opening prologue to the tale, Dayanand ponders the problem of whether religion (dharm) is one or many (ek v! anek), and, if it is many, whether its different sects are opposed to one another. If they are opposed, he writes, then without the first, the second religion cannot exist. [379] That is, in the oppositional arena of the polemic public, the true religion always comes second. It defines itself in relation to the lie and is therefore always the other, the supplement to that lie. With this maxim in mind (ek ke bin!, dusr! nahi# ho sakt!), the singularity of the single religion (the ek in ekmat ) starts to look a little strange. If truth can only exist in the secondness of the lie, then the ekmat cannot be the true religion. Rather, the lie is the first religion, and it serves a productive function. The lie allows truths to proliferate; it is the zero that begins the ordinal chain of nine hundred and ninety nine religions. And if the lie is the first religion (the ekmat), then it is the lie that stands at the center of the encircled assembly (the zero of the religious mandala) to call all the religions to order.
In this chapter, I have described how Swami Dayananda Saraswati s Saty"rth
Prak"sh uses the figure of the pope to explain the historical fall of Vedic Hinduism into Puranic heterodoxy. Dayanand wants to purge Hindu practice of sacerdotalism, image worship, caste bias, and hazily mystical ontologies all of which, as he tells it, arose in the debased Kali Yug. It is not surprising then that he has been so often hailed as the Luther of Modern India. I want to close my discussion by suggesting how Dayanand s neologism pope-lila both supports this appellation and calls it into question. On the one hand, of course, a neo-Vedic Hinduism pitched against the popes is by its very constitution Protestant. On the other hand, however, Dayanand, was quite careful to use a foreign term to traduce his opponents: heterodox Hindus, once dubbed popes, were forced into semantic exile. Their truth-seeking critics, meanwhile (the sattpur$%) remained firmly associated with India. To claim both sides of this conflict for Europe by hailing Dayanand as a Luther is to undo an important piece of his polemic project. As far as Dayanand was concerned, truth and the criticism of religion were innately Indian; it was the charlatanic parody of true religion that came from abroad to institute a regime of cultural hybridity.
Of course, I too have tried to deny Dayanand his desired purity. I have suggested that his pope-lila is, in the sense meant by Dilip Gaonkar, a creative adaptation of priestcraft. Dayanand used pope-lila to articulate an alternative anticlerical modernity and locate a distinctively Indian pre-history for the modern criticism of religion. He identifies Shankara as an indispensible forbearer to his neo-Vedic reforms, even while using the figure of the priestly imposter to reduce the scope of Vedantic maya: rather than producing the material world, and thus serving in a sense as the horizon of the real, illusion for Dayanand is simply deceit. It is a priestly ruse that must be dispelled before humanity can reclaim the true religion of the lost Vedic age. This is, to be sure, an Enlightenment Hinduism that forecasts a future brimming with right knowledge. But it is also, and I think more importantly, a critically hybrid Hinduism. The conjunctive hyphen in pope-lila allows Dayanand critical purchase on two imaginaries of illusion, allowing him to play the one off the other.
Dayanand was not the only theorist of priestly illusion and colonial encounter to visit Bombay in the 1870s. In 1878, the neo-Vedic reformer received a letter from a Russian noblewoman and an American colonel. In 1875, the same year that he had published the Saty"rth Prak"sh and founded the Arya Samaj, this eccentric duo had founded a group that they called the Theosophical Society. Its New York membership delighted in the occult, in spiritualistic experimentation, in comparative religion, and (increasingly) in the mystic East. It would be another year until H. P. Blavatsky and
Henry Steel Olcott relocated to Bombay, but when Dayanand replied to their letter, two of the decade s most important religious movements formed an uneasy alliance. If the two groups had less in common than their founders had originally thought, at least they shared a single enemy: Olcott s invectives against India s crafty and selfish priesthood proved just as caustic as Dayanand s diatribes against pope-lila. [380]
Blavastky, however, proved to be a problem. Within four years of that first letter, Dayanand decided that her interest in illusionism was very different from his own. And in a March 1882 speech entitled The Humbuggery of the Theosophists, the Swami went public with his suspicions. The speech accuses the Theosophists of embezzlement, religious fickleness, and intentional deceit. They were, Dayanand announced, no better than jugglers and magicians.[381] In other words, the Theosophists were to be classed with the popes. The next chapter turns from Dayanand to the alleged lila of his Theosophical acquaintances. In 1884, two years after his denunciatory speech, they found themselves embroiled in a momentous scandal that, as I will demonstrate, brought the question of religious imposture to vivid life.
Wherefore if they shall say unto you, Behold! He is in the secret chambers, believe it not. Matthew 24: 26 [382]
I believe, O Lord; help thou my unbelief. H. P. Blavatsky [383]
Whether celebrated as the mouthpiece of hidden seers or saluted as one of the most accomplished, ingenious, and interesting imposters in history, it is clear that Madame Helena Petrovna Blavatsky has earned a title to permanent remembrance in the annals of religious illusion.[384] Blavatsky distilled the core elements of the imposture narrative like few others, using imposture not only to question the epistemological procedures of the secular modern, but also to cast occult connections between colony and metropole. She was, in short, a skeptic s medium, whose career troubled the hoary conflict between doubt and belief by reimagining the associative possibilities of both. More than a century of writing has sought to define Blavatsky once and for all as either a conniving huckster or a martyred divine. My analysis will bypass this debate by interrogating the discursive conjuncture that made the question of fraud a resonant one in the 1880s (and afterwards). Rather than asking whether Blavatsky was an imposter, I will ask how multiple intersecting discourses produced imposture as a stock narrative for traducing religion. I will consider both how the imposture narrative overdetermined efforts to adjudicate the truth of Theosophical miracle and how it proved productive for Theosophists and their critics alike. If the perennial debate over Blavatsky s alleged fraud has proved anything, it is not her innocence nor her guilt, but rather the persistent appeal of the charlatan as a metonym for modernity and its anxieties about religion.
In order to trace the specific effects of the allegations of fraud against Blavatsky, I will analyze documents from the Coulomb Affair of 1884-85, the biggest scandal to shake the young Theosophical Society. Like the Maharaj Libel Affair, the Coulomb scandal assumed the proportions that it did precisely because of its ability to distill and dramatize the fundamental elements of the imposture narrative. The scandal centered not on the adjudication of truth, but rather on the spectacle of a potent modern mythology played out in print. The major parts (charlatan, dupe, critic) were known already; what remained to be seen was who would be cast in which role and how exactly the plot would unfold.
The Coulomb Affair was at its most interesting in the moments when the players either resisted their parts or attempted to negotiate the terms of the narrative. While the following discussion will highlight several such moments, none are more significant than Blavatsky s own experiments with the standard plotline of divine exposure. Where many critics have sought to explain Blavatsky by positing hidden motives behind her alleged impostures ( pecuniary gain, religious mania, the morbid yearning for notoriety, a secret life as a Russian spy),[385] I look to the surface of her apparent charlatanic performance to ask how she understood the role of imposter so often assigned to her. Blavatsky sought to explore the limits of credulity, opening religious imaginaries foreclosed by the usual binary of self-deceived idiots and
fraudulent imposters. 5
The analysis in this chapter contributes to what I see as a third wave in the literature on Blavatsky and the Theosophical Society. The first response to Theosophy has typically been to weigh its truth claims, both supernatural and philological, either alleging or denying fraudulence. A second wave of research distanced itself from the question of fraud in order to show how the Society served as an important nexus for the articulation of major cultural, political, and intellectual movements of its period, including feminism, anti-colonialism, Hindu reformism, Western Buddhism, Sri Lankan Protestant Buddhism, and post-Enlightenment esotericism.6 Particular attention has been paid to the Society s staggeringly transnational reach, which extended to the
United States, the United Kingdom, Ireland, France, Germany, Russia, India, Ceylon,
Indonesia, and elsewhere.7 This was a truly global religion fueled by cosmopolitan
5 Pall Mall Gazette, 23 October 1884, as quoted in The Theosophist, December 1884, 70.
6 Alex Owen, The Darkened Room: Women, Power and Spiritualism in Late Nineteenth Century England (London:
Virago, 1989); Alex Owen, The Place of Enchantment: British Occultism and the Culture of the Modern (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); Joy Dixon, Theosophy and Feminism in England (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins, 2001); Gauri Viswanathan, Conversion, Theosophy, and Race Theory, in Outside the Fold:
Conversion, Modernity, and Belief (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998), 177-208; Stephen R.
Prothero, The White Buddhist: The Asian Odyssey of Henry Steel Olcott (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996); Joscelyn Godwin, The Theosophical Enlightenment (Albany: State Unversity of New York Press, 1994); Peter Washington, Madame Blavatsky s Baboon: Theosophy and the Emergence of the Western Guru (London: Secker and Warburg, 1993); Molly McGarry, Ghosts of Futures Past: Spiritualism and the Cultural Politics of Nineteenth Century America (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008).
7 See, for instance, Maria Carlson, No Religion Higher Than Truth : A History of the Theosophical Movement in
Russia, 1875-1922 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); Herman A. O. de Tollenaere, The Politics of
Divine Wisdom: Theosophy and labour, national, and women s movements in Indonesia and South Asia, 1875-1947 (Leiden: Uitgeverij Katholieke Universiteit Nijmegan, 1996); Carla Risseuw Thinking culture through counter-culture: the case of theosophists in India and Ceylon and their ideas on race and hierarchy (1875-1947), in Gurus and their followers, ed. Antony Copley (New York: Oxford 2000); Laurie J. Sears,
Intellectuals, theosophy, and failed narratives of the nation in late colonial Java, in A Companion to Postcolonial Studies, ed. Henry Schwartz and Sangeeta Ray (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2000); Edward C.
ideals, and, as such, it warrants inclusion in histories of globalization and global cultural forms.
More recently, a handful of literary scholars have returned to the more hotly contested aspects of Theosophy, but in doing so have resisted the hackneyed debate about fraud.8 Rather, their work has begun to develop a more sophisticated hermeneutic for interpreting Blavatskyian occultism, whether by replacing the notion of fraudulence with notions of prosthesis, simulation, and plagiarism ; by reconsidering the political valence of conversion and belief; or by revisiting the loquacious Mahatmas and the modes of literary subjectivity modeled in their letters.9 My analysis will expand on what I take to be a major implication of this work: that it is high time we revisited questions of fraud and false belief. I do so by delineating the precise notions of fraudulence that were available to participants in the Coulomb
Affair, particularly in India.10
Moulton, The Beginnings of the Theosophical Movement in India, 1879-1885: Conversion and NonConversion Experiences, in Religious Conversion Movements in South Asia: Continuities and Change, 1800-1900, ed. Geoffrey A. Oddie (Richmond, Surrey: Curzon Press, 1997), 109-172.
8 Gauri Viswanathan, The Ordinary Business of Occultism, Criticial Inquiry 27 (Autumn 2000): 1-20; Srinivas Aravamudan, Guru English: South Asian Religion in a Cosmopolitan Language (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006).
9 Aravamudan, Guru English, 106
10 While the Coulomb Affair should also be understood as part of a larger history of occultism in colonial India, that history has not (to my knowledge) been written, and doing so is well beyond the scope of this chapter. Suffice it to say that the same sorts of experiments in mesmerism, s ances, ghosts, and spirits that proved popular in the North Atlantic countries also enjoyed some cachet among Anglo-Indians. Some examples: In 1847, a Bombay dentist (one Dr. H. Miller) successfully mesmerized his patient before removing twelve of her teeth (Bombay Times and Courier, June 9, 1847). A Calcutta debating society concluded that the dead do in fact sometimes visit the living (Poona Observer, June 18, 1861). The Bombay Gazette reported on the table rapping humbug, Mr. Foster, currently the rage in London (Bombay
Gazette, April 11, 1862). A small s ance in Poona drew forth the spirit of Cagliostro ( S ance in Poona, Bombay Gazette, May 12, 1862). And in the same month, a Sindhi newspaper compared a sayyid s intervention with Pir Ghazi to the fashionable London s ances of Mr. Foster, the Yankee imposter ( Spiritualism in Sind, The Sindian, May 21, 1862; reproduced in Bombay Gazette June 2, 1862).
Imposture implies exposure, the unveiling of the charlatan s fraud; and the trope of exposure was, in turn, predicated on ideas about publicity and the public sphere. As I will suggest, just as Blavatsky experimented with the standard narrative of false belief, she also experimented with the limits of publicity and public knowledge. Theosophy demonstrates that public spheres, rather than being natural or inevitable, emerge as imagined and idiosyncratic fields, wherein social space is not only always curved, [386] but also in constant flux. Ghostlike, they materialize at a properly voiced incantation, but they also dissipate just as quickly. There is perhaps no pithier expression of this paradigm than Theosophical co-founder Henry Steel Olcott s quip about the global brotherhood of man: Theosophy is the enchantress who alone can conjure it up. [387] Publics are phantom entities, conjured by sorcerer institutions.
Publics have also been said to rely on an open spirit, and it is the presumption of public openness that will occupy the bulk of my attention here. The Coulomb Affair was nothing if not a contestation over the proprieties of exposing religion to public scrutiny. The following discussion will demonstrate how participants in the Affair invoked an ethic of openness, wielding it against the fake religion of their rivals and inflecting it with their own devotional idioms, always anchoring the public imaginary in that which exceeds and eludes it Truth, God, miracle.
The first part of the chapter is largely descriptive. Its three short sections narrate the Coulomb Affair ( Isis Very Much Unveiled ); note the short-lived possibility that Blavatsky, like Jadunathji Maharaj before her, would file a libel suit against her journalistic attacker ( Courting Libel ); and chart the basic contours of the colonial public within which the affair unfolded ( Curvatures of the Colonial Public ). Readers already familiar with the Coulomb Affair, or otherwise impatient with expository detail, may want to skip the first two sections in particular.
The principle analysis comes in the second part of the chapter. There, five sections develop a series of interlinked arguments. First (in Confessing the Faith ), I suggest that Indian Theosophists were doubly bound by imperial ideologies that pushed Indian politics to the private domain of religion, while simultaneously constraining religious belief with the stereotype of the credulous Hindu. The section concludes with an analysis of how one Bengali Theosophist (Mohini Chatterjee) tried to intervene in the discursive constitution of belief by placing renewed emphasis on
trust in the guru. Second ( Dialectics of Enlightenment ), I track how the Theosophists appropriated the conflict narrative of Science and Religion, as articulated by John William Draper, by positing Theosophy as the synthesis of the two. I further suggest that, particularly during the Coulomb Affair, this dialectic was intertwined with the related interplay of concealment and openness.
Third ( Epistemologies of Exposure ), I describe how scientists, missionaries, and Theosophists all espoused an ethic of openness. That is, they all repeatedly invoked the idea that religion must lay itself bare to the scrutinizing attention of the critical public if it is to avoid the moral ills of priestcraft. Fourth ( Epistemology of the Veil ), I argue that Blavatsky tried to articulate an alternative to the epistemology of exposure in her occult meditations on the hidden life of spirits. Her epistemology of the veil promised both closure and openness simultaneously, an experiment in occult knowledge that sought to interrupt the public certainties promised by the exposure narrative. For Blavatsky, the cloaked lie was subsumed, not displaced, by the naked truth. Finally, by way of conclusion ( Signs Taken for Wonders ), I use a period book review to theorize miracle as that which refuses to unveil itself fully to the knowing
Madame Helena Petrovna Blavatsky had been in a dreadful state all day, [388] her corpulent, gout-stricken frame rattled by bad news from India. A prodding telegram, a lugubrious letter, [389] a friend fresh from Suez: the fast-moving missives of nineteenthcentury modernity had overtaken her on her European tour, and they brought ill tidings. Madame Blavatsky had been betrayed.
Emma Coulomb, her trusted secretary and an old friend from back in her Cairo days, had violated the trust not only of Blavatsky, but of the entire Theosophical Society. Since her appearance in Bombay over four years previously (March 1880), with her husband Pierre in tow, Emma had proved an unruly and often unorthodox
Theosophist. The mounting antagonism between her and the other members of the
Society had come to a head that May (1884), when an emergency meeting voted to eject her from campus for slandering Blavatsky. Now, in September, those slanders had exploded into a scandal that would shake the status of the Theosophical Society as a preeminent peddler of the global occult.
An angry Emma had delivered to the Madras Christian College Magazine a set of letters, ostensibly sent to her by Blavatsky. They offered a basic course in divine theatrics; dating back several years, the letters explicitly instructed Coulomb in how to stage phenomena for Theosophists and possible converts to the cause (particularly those with deep pockets, like Jacob Sassoon, the Bombay tycoon), telling her where and when Koot Hoomi and the other Mahatmas should manifest their astral forms
(their physical bodies remaining in Tibet) and where and when they should
precipitate letters. According to Coulomb, the extraordinary events that had followed in Blavatsky s wake roses raining from palace ceilings, heads wafting through tropical evenings, letters careening into railway windows, teacups surfacing from virgin ground had never been anything but the basest hokum. Even Blavatsky s revered Shrine Room, centered on the Cabinet of Wonders, had been specially engineered by
Pierre to enable imposture.
Reverend George Patterson, published Coulomb s letters under the salacious title The Collapse of Koot Hoomi. Patterson s purported exposure of Blavatsky, with its frequent appeals to public duty, prodded readers curiosity into a sustained scandal an avalanche of prose would weigh the plausibility of miracle and the culpability of miracle-makers. A few newspapers defended Theosophy, maintaining of the Coulomb allegation that prima facie it is worthless. [390] Most, however, gleefully dissected Blavatsky s modern miracles. London s Graphic reported that Koot Hoomi s astral body had been nothing more than a crafty arrangement of bladders, muslin, and a mask, while the wonder-working shrine at Madras was no more than an ordinary conjuror s cabinet. [391] Other papers went still further in denouncing miracle-mongering by predicting that [s]o complete is the exposure of Madame Blavatsky and her miracles that the Theosophical Society is now done for; [392] by celebrating Patterson s good and courageous service in thus unmasking what seems to be no other than a gigantic fraud, and so emancipating the country from what was fast becoming a cruel superstition; [393] or, more pruriently, reporting that Isis has again been unveiled. The goddess has been exposed in all her nakedness, and the great Koot Hoomi has fallen upon his face. [394]
In November 1884, young Australian researcher Richard Hodgson, emissary of Cambridge s Society for Psychical Research (S.P.R.), arrived at the Society s Madras headquarters to conduct a scientific investigation of the phenomena, as part of a broader inquiry into the supernatural claims of religion per se.[395] Before Hodgson s visit, the Theosophists had been very friendly with the S.P.R., praising it in print and even volunteering to be interviewed at its London office.21 This period of amity, however, drew to an emphatic close in spring 1885, when the S.P.R. published Hodgson s report on the Theosophical Society. The Report s conclusion has generally been taken as the resounding final word on Blavatsky and the Coulomb Affair: For our own part, we regard her neither as the mouthpiece of hidden seers, nor as a mere vulgar adventuress; we think that she has achieved a title to permanent remembrance as one of the most accomplished, ingenious, and interesting imposters in history. 22
Miracle had clearly gotten lost in the mail, and, with it, Blavatsky s role as divine postwoman. Despite Theosophists frequent protests to the contrary, the lure of the phenomena, in all their ambiguity, had anchored the Society s occult intervention into the discursive field of world religions. Theosophy had promised unique access to a single truth underlying all religious systems, and it had vowed that, under its watch, no religion would climb higher than this truth. If its occult spaces harbored not divine verities, but rather all-too-human deceptions, this core Theosophical contract would be rendered null and void.
investigation within its larger project, see Edmund Gurney, Frederic W. H. Myers, and Frank Podmore, Phantasms of the Living, vol.1 (Gainesville, FL: Scholars Fascimiles and Reprints, 1970 [1886]), xlvi-lvii.
21 As late as October 1884, The Theosophist had looked forward to the day when, thanks to the S.P.R., scientific authority would finally concede the so long pooh-poohed phenomena of mind ; The Theosophist 1.10 (October 1884): 21. In May and June 1884, Henry Steel Olcott, Alfred Percy Sinnett, and
Mohini Chatterjee had been interviewed by the S.P.R. during their sojourn in England. See SPR.MS.4/1/14/1/4
22 SPR Proceedings, 207.
The great religious scandal of the 1860s (the Maharaj Libel Affair) assumed the proportions that it did because it was played out in the Bombay High Court. Karsandas
Mulji defamed Vallabhac!rya Maharaj Jadunathji Brizratanji in his newspaper, the Satya Prakash, and Jadunath sued him for libel. The court then had to decide whether the libel was justified that is, whether the Maharaj had done the terrible things that Mulji had alleged. In the process, it found itself adjudicating the authenticity of an entire religious sect.
The Coulomb Affair could well have developed along parallel lines. Patterson defamed Blavatsky, and she in turn could have sued him for libel. Indeed, when she arrived in India in December 1884, she seemed determined to do just that. While still in London, she had resolved to prosecute Patterson and the Coulombs, and so on her way to India she stopped off in Cairo, the city where she had first met Emma. She telegraphed Olcott from Cairo to tell him that she had successfully gathered legal proofs that the Coulombs had fled Egypt to escape arrest for fraudulent bankruptcy.
But once she finally arrived in Madras, Olcott was dismayed at the quality of her proofs.
Acting without legal advice, he wrote, she had made a mess of the affair. Although Blavatsky kept badgering Olcott to take her to a judge, or solicitor, or barrister, no matter which, he demurred, insisting that before she file an affidavit, she wait for the Annual Convention of the Theosophical Society. There, a special committee could decide the best course of action.[396]
On December 27, 1884, Olcott opened the Convention with his inaugural address. Before referring the problem to the special committee, he noted that the vast majority of our members throughout the world have expressed a decided objection to filing suit against Coulomb and Patterson. Like them, he thinks it will be impossible to avoid having the trial of Madame Blavatsky s reputation turned into a trial of the truth of the Esoteric Philosophy and the existence of the Mahatmas. Such sacred subjects should not be surrendered to the courts. Moreover, Anglo-Indian attorneys would be given the utmost latitude to goad to desperation our witnesses, especially Madame Blavatsky, whose extreme nervousness and excitability all know. A trial would be disastrous for Theosophy s public image, and this, Olcott thinks, is exactly why a trial is what Theosophy s enemies want most. At all costs, Blavatsky must be kept out of the witness box.[397]
The special committee came to more or less the same conclusion.[398] They chewed on Madras gossip, repeating an overheard conversation in which an influential citizen said he hoped Blavatsky would bring an action so that this d---d fraud may be shown up, and it is not at all impossible that she may be sent to the Andaman Islands. They weighed legal precedent, notably a libel case brought by Bengali reformer Keshab Chander Sen (cousin to the committee chair) and concluded that, at least in India, the position of plaintiff in a libel case is a dangerous one. They unanimously recommended that Blavatsky not prosecute, and their recommendation was adopted (again unanimously) by the Convention s assembled delegates.[399] Thus and despite a shortlived attempt by Coulomb to bring her own libel suit against the Theosophist General Morgan, intending to subpoena Blavatsky in the process the Society managed to keep Theosophy out of court.
Instead, it would be tried by the court of public opinion. Indeed, one notable feature of the Coulomb Affair is the pervasiveness of legalistic language in the public debate. Court or no court, juridical procedures were the order of the day. The S.P.R. canvassed Theosophical witnesses for testimonies about Blavatsky s alleged miracles, while the likewise newspapers presented proofs to the court of public opinion. Theosophist Subramania Iyer argued that this dissemination of the juridical function from the state to the citizens would further the formation of autonomous liberal subjects. As he wrote, every reasonable man is at liberty to form an opinion on the evidence placed before him and should not surrender this capacity of judgment to the verdict of a Court of Justice. [400] Iyer s claim secured the privacy of belief and argued for its invulnerability to interference from the colonial government or other institutions.
The court of public opinion hailed by the Coulomb Affair was defined by a very particular medium (print) and a very particular historical condition (colonialism). The Affair raged primarily within the Anglophone print sphere, testing that sphere s global reach; but its debates also entered publics defined by other languages, including the colonized vernacular tongues against which English defined itself as cosmopolitan.
The scandal, of course, borrowed its basic contours from the occult counterpublic forged by Theosophy itself.[401] The Theosophical Society had mapped its occult world through an epic endeavor in publicity, laboring for what A. P. Sinnett termed the propagation of occult truths. [402] The dual commitment to secrecy and publicity was often an uneasy one for the Theosophists. There were those who worried that the very existence of the Theosophical Society was a transgression of sorts; that the Adepts, in authorizing Blavatsky to bring their teachings to the masses, had violated the esoteric code. The ambiguities of occult publicity also befuddled the S.P.R. As J. Herbert Stack wrote to Henry Sidgwick, why all these publications and lectures and private efforts at propaganda? Why try to convert the West at all if they are resolved to remain wrapped in Oriental dignity? [403]
Such contradictions, however, seem only to have incited more speech: from
Blavatsky forward, the Theosophists have been a prolix bunch, producing thousands of printed pages in several genres not only Blavatskyian tomes, but also pamphlets, magazines, biographies, letters, speeches, and even novels. Although it was always accompanied by other modes of publicity (lectures, conventions, phenomena ), print publishing was surely the quintessential Theosophical task, with no publication more central to the Society s mission than its flagship journal, The Theosophist, launched from
Bombay in September 1879.31
From the first, the polyglot Theosophical public found itself occupying and occupied by a language that was, for many voices, never quite comfortable. Even Blavatsky herself confessed that, when writing Isis Unveiled (1877), English was still very much a language foreign to me in which I had not been accustomed to write. 32
Throughout her life, she seems to have remained more at ease in Russian and French. If
Koot Hoomi appeared in her dreams to mock her Funny English as only a little
31 In order to get a better sense of the sort of publishing activity that the Coulomb Affair disrupted, one might note the contents of The Theosophist s September 1884 issue, fated to be eclipsed by the Madras Christian Magazine s expos . There are articles by prominent Theosophists like Mohini Chatterjee
( Qualifications for Chelaship, previously a talk given to the London Lodge) and Henry Steel Olcott ( The Dangers of Black Magic ), as well as extracts from non-Theosophical publications. There are extracts from the Buddhist Dhammapada; an essay on Ancient Occultism in Caledonia ; and a piece on The Buddhist Heaven, reprinted from The Statesman. Additional articles treat topics as diverse as the Count de St. German (an alleged occultist), posthumous visitations, European Theosophy, and the history of magic. There are extensive extracts from European papers, as well as series of letters to the editor one of which describes a thelemometer, or will measurer. One article (about an epidemic of thought-reading in Paris) was translated from a Swedish magazine. Two previous challenges to Theosophical truth are disputed in this issue of the magazine: the Kiddle Incident (in which Master Koot
Hoomi inadvertently plagiarized a speech given by an American, Mr. Kiddle, in upstate New York) and
Arthur Lillie s pamphlet Koot Hoomi Unveiled. The latter picked apart the scholarship of Blavatsky s Isis Unveiled and Sinnett s Occult World and Esoteric Buddhism; it argued that Esoteric Buddhism was hardly Buddhist at all. [See Arthur Lillie, Koot Hoomi Unveiled; or Tibeten Buddhists versus the Buddhists of Tibet (London: Psychological Press Association, c.1884)]. See The Theosophist 1.9 (September 1884).
32 The Theosophist, January 1886, 279, as quoted by Boris de Zirkoff, How Isis Unveiled was Written, in Isis Unveiled, Helena Petrovna Blavatsky, ed. Boris de Zirkoff, 2 vols. (Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2006), 45.
worse than his own, it was to emphasize her pidgin kinship with the astral babu.33 Theosophy s guru English, unevenly inflected with (to name only the languages that impinge directly on this scandal) Russian, French, German, Tamil, Telugu, Gujarati, and Marathi, clearly allowed for the articulation of discrepant cosmopolitan identities not entirely assimilable to imperial projects.34 But a Theosophy voiced in English could never hail a neutral public. The language of which it was born determined its peculiar colonial resonances, the knowledges that were legible to it, and those that must forever remain veiled.
Accordingly, coverage of the Coulomb Affair was most intensive in the Englishlanguage press. The scandal took shape in Anglophone ink in Madras, Bombay, Calcutta, London, Liverpool, Pittsburgh, Melbourne, and elsewhere. In addition to inciting spirited debate in Theosophical and missionary periodicals and pamphlets, the scandal saw regular coverage in major Anglo-Indian dailies like Madras s Times and Mail; Bombay s Times of India, Guardian, and Mahratta; Bangalore s Post and Spectator;
Allahabad s Pioneer; and Calcutta s Statesman, Friend of India, Englishman, and Indian Daily News. While some papers vigorously attacked Theosophy (e.g the Times of India), others withheld judgment until the authenticity of the letters could be proved (e.g. the
Mahratta) or worried about the precedent set by this incautious publication of private
33 The striking similarity of Blavatsky s and Koot Hoomi s English would be highlighted during the
Coulomb Affair and S.P.R. investigation, proving useful fodder for those intent on collapsing the
Mahatma into his amanuensis. Their shared Gallicisms, for instance, such as spelling skeptic with a
c, seemed incontrovertible proof of their identity. Blavatsky s defense: I have learned my English from Him! H. P. Blavatsky to A. P. Sinnett, January 6, 1886 (ML-140), Mahatma Letters, 453-457
34 Aravamudan, Guru English, 3.
letters (the Madras Mail).[404] Papers during the period reprinted each other s work routinely, and the resultant rapid recycling of journalistic prose was a necessary precondition of this and other scandals. Indeed, The Theosophist, in October 1884, accused the Madras Christian College Magazine of having manipulated this system to engineer the scandal; Patterson, it seems had distributed advance proof sheets to newspapers throughout India in order to create a general and simultaneous howl against the Society. [405]
The geographic scope of the scandal indicates the extent of global interconnections among Anglophone reading publics of the period. It also suggests the importance of religious institutions in establishing such connections and incorporating local publics into global communities. Pittsburgh s Presbyterian Banner, for instance, energetically derided the distant Theosophists and proclaimed that the Christian world is indebted for the complete investigation that resulted in the entire demolition of Theosophy s truth claims.[406] Over the next few years, other papers in cities as far-flung as Melbourne and Boston would join the debate about Blavatsky.[407] The Indian vernacular press seems to have shown less interest in the Coulomb Affair.[408] At least one dual language paper the Dnyanodaya positioned the scandal as appealing only to readers of English. Despite commonly providing double coverage of stories in both Marathi and English, this missionary journal discussed Theosophy only in its English columns.[409] The article reporting the Coulomb letters laments that although this revelation should explode the faith of all in this imposture, the infatuated Theosophists will likely persist in their faith; the missionaries only hope is that Indians will in future be more suspicious of those who would flatter Indian religions at the expense of Christianity.[410] If the linguistic medium is part of the message, then the Dyanodaya implies that Anglophone Indians were most at risk of succumbing to such flattery.
Some vernacular papers did clearly assume that their readers would follow the Affair. Bombay s Parsi-run, Gujarati-language Satiya Mitar (Friend of Truth), for instance, reported on the Coulomb letters, although not as extensively as did its Englishlanguage contemporaries. Two short articles reported the bare facts of the case, apparently assuming some background knowledge on the part of readers.[411] This assumption would surely have been warranted, as the Theosophical Society had broadcast its support for Zoroastrianism since 1879, even translating one of Olcott s speeches on Zarathustra into Gujarati.[412] It is also likely that the Affair s anti-clerical subtext (see below) would have resonated with Bombay s Parsis. A letter published in the Satiya Mitar on November 1884 (two months into the Affair) censured the onslaught of Christian priests ( kr$.)ian p!-rio ) intent on planting in the minds of Parsi youth the poison of infidelity ( p!r.$on$ chokr$on!# manm!# beim!n$nu jehar d!khal
kar$ ).[413]
Conditions of colonialism shaped not only the form of the scandal which public venues it entered, and which it did not but also its content. From the start, Emma Coulomb paired her accusations of fraud with accusations that Blavatsky had agitated against British rule.[414] As the Affair progressed, this charge played itself out in a series of gossipy anecdotes about both women while Blavatsky was famed for her surliness toward the British, Coulomb was said to keep a pack of mangy dogs to worry the brahmans. Blavatsky s renowned support for all things Indian won her both friends and foes. Perhaps most dramatically, when she returned at last to Madras on 21 December 1884, she disembarked to a cheering delegation of students who welcomed her
return from the intellectual campaigns waged in the West and proclaimed India s
immense debt of endless gratitude to her. A written statement of these sentiments was signed by more than three hundred students of the colleges of Madras, including Madras Christian College although at least one newspaper account claims that such signatures could be acquired under false pretenses.[415]
Alongside colonialism, gender too shaped the public sphere conjured by the
Coulomb Affair. While women and men both participated in the discussions about Coulomb and Blavastky, gender often coded the scandalous trajectories of their public careers. Gendered rhetoric determined the debate over the authenticity of the Coulomb letters in very concrete ways: handwriting expert J. D. B. Gribble attested that Emma Coulomb, with her essentially feminine hand could never have mimicked the bold, free running masculine hand of Blavatsky.[416] In more general terms, several participants imbued the entire public arena with a masculine ethos. Theosophist H. R. Morgan, for example, invested the public sphere with a martial masculinity: Gribble becomes the chivalrous knight of the missionaries, taking up the gauge of the opposition despite the risk of being struck on the helmet, and hurled to the ground. [417] Morgan further compares the entire missionary party to the gladiators of old, who would exclaim in the arena of public opinion, Ave Caesar morituri te salutant, and forthwith perform the act of Hari-kari. [418]
Class also played a role. The most visible participants in the Affair occupied fairly elite social positions and, not coincidentally, were disproportionately employed in the Anglophone service professions that abutted the British imperial government
(lawyers loom large here). The major exception to this rule seems to have been Babula,
Blavatsky s personal servant, rumored to have once worked for a French conjuror. [419] Hodgson once remarked that, as a servant, he would have been in the perfect position to perpetrate frauds. Servants, like Mahatmas, spend much of their lives cloaked in partial invisibility.
It was to this public, demarcated and defined by gender, language, class, and coloniality, that Patterson appealed in his expos of Blavatsky. Its specific curvatures determined not only the shape of his call for truth and scrutiny, but also the discursive positions available to his would-be opponents.
At a fundamental level, the Coulomb Affair centered on the pertinence of belief as social fact, its scandal resisting the secularizing logic that would relegate religion to private liberties. Patterson urged the public to discipline religion, implying that false faiths endanger the social body and therefore must be eradicated.
Not everyone readily conceded the right of public institutions to regulate faith, however, and some of the most impassioned resistance came from Indian Theosophists.
Judge Sreenevasa Row, for instance, argued that Patterson has no right to make allusions in public prints to my faith in spiritual matters, much less to find fault with it, and much less still to suggest that the so called exposure ought to effect a change in my views. Row derided Patterson s very peculiar notion of public duty, demanding,
What does the public care which faith an individual in the world belongs to? [420]
One might, following Partha Chatterjee, read Row s resistance to rendering religion public as tied to broader attempts on the part of Indian elites to demarcate a domain of sovereignty free from British influence.[421] In this reconstituted private arena, bourgeois Indian men could assert their dominance, despite public political venues having been usurped by the colonizers (a move with decidedly ambivalent effects on Indian women). The publishing interests of many of the older recruits, already classically educated before entering the Theosophical fold, bear out this suggestion. The Society and its journal provided an important institutional space for the translation, rejuvenation, and consolidation of Hinduism, often with little or no reference to Blavatsky s teachings. Patterson s effort to claim belief as a matter of public concern would have compromised the emergent political formation that had taken shelter in Theosophy s occult spaces.
The ideologies of empire were, however, treacherously plural, such that public professions of belief by Hindu Theosophists, no matter how savvy or politicized, inevitably corroborated a colonial stereotype central to the unfolding of the Affair: that of the credulous native. Propounded by missionaries throughout the earlier part of the nineteenth century, this racist discourse maintained that Indians were more prone toward religious gullibility than were Westerners.
This discourse entered the Coulomb Affair in all kinds of ways. It colored the
S.P.R. s purportedly neutral investigation of Theosophy, as is evidenced by Herbert Stack s suggestion, in a letter to Henry Sidgwick, that Theosophy s rapid progress amongst uneducated, superstitious, and credulous natives is prima facie against it [422]; and by Richard Hodgson s claim, based on a comparison of hypnosis research in London and Calcutta, that whenever possible psychical researchers should experiment on Orientals because they are more susceptible to mental manipulation.[423] It disrupted the solidarity between foreign and Indian Theosophists, as when Franz Hartmann complained to Hodgson of the superstitious awe with which Damodar Mavalankar regarded Blavatsky s occult shrine, or when St. George Lane-Fox dismissed all testimony about the Shrine by native witnesses due to the exceeding reverence in which they universally hold it.[424]
It certainly informed the opinions of the British press. Especially egregious was
an article in London s Graphic that, comparing Theosophists reverence for the altar
at Madras to the adoration of the natives prostrate before a peepul tree, faulted educated Indians for their regression back to the absurdities of their ancient superstitions via Theosophical fraud and imposture. [425] Indian fanaticism is the constant foil for a sober Euro-American rationality, and the anxious repetition of this stereotyped difference implies its innate instability particularly evident in the case of
Theosophy, which had fascinated British and Indian alike. [426]
The stereotypes of native credulity circumscribed the range of public actions available to the elite Indian men involved in the Theosophical Society and ensured that their public confessions of faith were overdetermined by multiple, competing imperial discourses. But just as their espousal of Theosophy indicated a canny awareness of how the transcendent sphere intersected with worldly politics, so too did their public avowal of belief allow them to reshape that volatile, ideological term.
All of this was especially relevant to the public personas of the enthusiastic younger converts to Theosophy like Damodar Mavalankar and Mohini Chatterjee.[427] Chatterjee was particularly keen on playing languages against each other both to redefine belief and to disrupt efforts to document it (as when he used his defective
English to frustrate Richard Hodgson s investigations).[428] In a September 1884 lecture, Chatterjee explicated the Sanskrit word .raddh! in order to demonstrate that unswerving confidence in the master is not required as a means to build up a system of priestcraft. Properly understood, .raddh! places equal emphasis on the master s power to teach and the pupil s power to learn and perform independent investigation. To accept any authority as final, and to dispense with the necessity of independent investigation is destructive of progress. Nothing, in fact, should be taken upon blind, unquestioning faith. 60
A letter that Chatterjee later submitted to London s Pall Mall Gazette indicates something of both the recalcitrance and the limited pliability of the discourse of belief. Chatterjee claimed that to a Brahman, like myself, it is repugnant to speak of the sacredly confidential relationship existing between a spiritual teacher and his pupil. The faith that happily renders an account of itself via profane speech is no faith at all. In the current case, however, duty compels Chatterjee to compromise his sacred bond by averring in public print that I have personal and absolute knowledge of the existence of the Mahatma Koot Hoomi. I had knowledge of the Mahatma in question before I knew Madame Blavatsky. 61
Chatterjee appeals to the inviolability of tradition by describing his reluctance to speak his faith as a brahman peccadillo. He thereby bolsters the boundaries of the
English: when he said he had been sitting on a rock when he saw the Mahatma, he had meant that he was sitting on the verandah. SPR Proceedings, 240-41.
60 Mohini Chatterjee, Qualifications of Chelaship, The Theosophist, September 1884, 281-283. Ibid, 282.
This speech was reprinted in Man: Fragments of a Forgotten History by Two Chelas in the Theosophical Society (London: Reeves and Turner, 1885). Alongside his evident Sanskritic erudtion, Chatterjee quotes approvingly from Lord Byron s poem The Giaour : Yes, self abasement leads the way/ To villain bonds and despot s sway.
61 Hodgson, First Report, 100.
privatized, ostensibly uncolonized spiritual sphere through an appeal to the colonial logic of non-interference in Indian custom. But for Chatterjee, this appeal to caste and tradition is also very personal: he surely invokes his caste status to recoup some of what was lost when he joined the Theosophical movement. He admits to having lost all my worldly prospects in Calcutta as a result of his unorthodox chelaship. Disowned at home for hitching himself to a firangi guru, he manages to repatriate his religion while residing in England. His true guru is not Blavatsky, but Koot Hoomi, and his astral discipleship predates his relations with that irascible Russian. Theosophy retreats into a realm inaccessible to the Anglophone public figured by the imagined landscapes of Tibet but well-known to the bilingual, high-caste Bengali.
Chatterjee s insistence on the primacy of the guru-chela relationship also subtly shifts the focus of the Affair. Here, the faith that matters is not faith in theological propositions or miraculous events but rather faith in persons not belief in dogma, but trust in the guru.[429] I would tentatively suggest that Chatterjee speaks between idioms, engaging both the dominant propositional mode of the scandal and his personal twist on it, when he swears to Koot Hoomi s reality. On the one hand is a concern with the possibility of the Mahatmas per se, and on the other a chela s love for his guru the gap between a factual knowledge of the Master s existence and a personal knowledge of the Mahatma himself. Whereas the propositional mode enjoins the public avowal of belief, the personal mode not only shuns publicity, it finds that it cannot speak itself adequately; it can only love and be silent.
By the 1880s, prominent voices in the Anglophone world had set out to refuse religion its silence and to reinforce the notion that faith is no more than the propositional tenets of belief. At the inception of the Theosophical Society, in New York in 1875, one such voice dominated discussions of the future of religion. New York University chemist John William Draper s polemic History of the Conflict between Religion and Science (1874) pitted scientific underdogs (Copernicus, Galileo) against a corrupt Church that spurns truth in favor of fallacious dogma. His book provided ample rhetorical fodder for Theosophists frustrated both with the Church and with the brash scientific confidence displayed by Draper himself; early Theosophical writings frequently quoted Draper while articulating their own offmodern slant on this most modern of narratives.[430]
In his History s culminating pages, Draper offers some very suggestive thoughts on the certain outcome of the conflict between science and religion: Whatever is resting on fiction and fraud will be overthrown. Institutions that organize impostures and spread delusions must show what right they have to exist. Faith must render an account of herself to Reason. Mysteries must give place to facts. [431] According to Draper, mystery, fiction, fraud, and imposture all of a piece with faith must compulsorily surrender themselves to fact, and they must do so through an act of confession.
Religion must, in Draper s words, render an account of herself ; she must show herself to an avowedly rational public. It is this exposure and this verbal representation of religion that, in Draper s narrative, secure the inevitable overthrow of a perfidious and fraudulent Faith. The injustices of institutional religion can only be undone by subordinating the faculty of faith to that of scientific reason, and this reordering of the faculties occurs via the personal exposure entailed by public speech. This exposure, of course, tended to reinforce other lines of injustice, as a feminized, colonized religion was forced to render an account of itself to a masculinized, Western rationality.
The Theosophical Society had set out to remake this dialectic of disenchantment. As Olcott once put it, if the laboratory-men were daily exposing the falsehood of theological dogma and so gaining power over the church-men, Theosophy would arrest the consequent ascent of atheism and materialism by articulating a new breed of faith. It would serve at once as the equilibrating opponent of materialistic science and the unmasker and natural foe of Christian theology. [432] Blavatsky likewise sought to synthesize Science and Religion; she aimed not only to broker a truce between the two foes, but also to uncover truths foreseen by neither. The importance of this dialectic to her thought is nowhere more evident than in the structure of Isis Unveiled. She tellingly split the tome into two volumes, Science and Theology, the warring halves of which are subsumed by the Theosophical whole. This dialectic logic emerges again in the Coulomb Affair, which hinged on the competition of three institutions: one proudly religious (the Magazine), one avowedly scientific (the S.P.R.), and one an ostensible synthesis of the two (the T.S.). And, crucially, publicity the willingness to render a public account of oneself serves as a litmus test for differentiating the three.
Draper would surely have appreciated that the S.P.R. espoused a rigorous ethic of openness, linking its scientific credentials to its fervor for public speech. A preliminary S.P.R. report, for instance, deployed this ethic to distinguish science from the occult. While the Theosophical Society advocates the concealment of knowledge from even friendly inquirers, the S.P.R. seeks to to scrutinize all that is revealed. Unlike its esoteric cousin, it is first and foremost a machinery for investigation, every step of which is open to the public. In this crucial respect, despite their overlap of interests, the two societies are almost diametrical. [433]
One might interpret the Coulomb Affair as an exemplary episode in the muchlauded epochal shift from Religion to Science, from Concealment to Openness. In the scandal, fiction and fraud gave way to fact, and the mysterious and miraculous to the merely mundane. But so facile a reading flattens the complexities of the Affair and the ambiguous trajectories of modern religion more broadly. The Coulomb Affair complicates Draper s conflict narrative in a variety of ways. First, it suggests how the narrative was appropriable by religious actors themselves, and how such actors could refashion its binary logic, as with the three-termed Theosophical dialectic (Christianity-Science-Theosophy, itself quickly unmoored). Second, it suggests that scientific and Christian institutions could work in tandem to secure their paired hegemonies against intruders, both Theosophical and Hindu.
Third, the Affair demonstrates how the conflict between Religion and Science was articulated across the subtler binary of Concealment and Openness. In the Coulomb Affair, the dialectic of disenchantment was structured by dueling ethics of veiling and exposure, or competing modes of publicness, [434] as promoted by a range of religious and secular institutions. Foremost among these modes of publicness were what I will term epistemologies of exposure and epistemologies of the veil.
Rev. Patterson framed his journalistic expos as an act of public duty. By his own account, he resolved in the interests of public morality to publish Emma Coulomb s letters, while prudently omitting purely private passages. To speak out was to disabuse a public which both in its Native and in its European contingents, has been so completely hoodwinked. Patterson positions his paper as a pedagogic instrument, guiding the credulous Indian masses, prone to falsehood, toward the light of Christian truth as propounded by the Christian skeptic. [435]
Patterson textures his appeal to the reading public by invoking older spectacular modalities of belief and disillusionment. He facetiously asserts that the oracle at Delphi has been dumb for many a century, by Urim and Thurim there is no response, but the shrine of Koot Hoomi still exists and the oracle of Adyar is not dumb (i.e., it, or she, is neither mute nor stupid). Patterson plays his double entendre well, asking: what if these signs and wonders are proof of something very different . Instead of a message from beings of supernal wisdom and power, we shall have only the private thoughts of a clever but not over scrupulous woman. [436] Patterson here inserts Blavatsky into a grand narrative of divine silence.
The muting of God had, since at least the late seventeenth century, provided a popular secularizing mythology for believers and materialists alike. It lent itself well to spectacular, pedagogic entertainments, such as reconstructions of classical oracles that were designed to reveal the priestly trickery that had, presumably, propped up paganism. It had also become an indispensible tool for colonial missionaries out to extinguish idolatrous heathenism. [437] This narrative of divine silence clearly lent itself better to missionary endeavor than did, say, Draper s conflict narrative; it provided clear justification for both the debunking of strangers worldly gods and the supremacy of Christianity s own transcendent divine. Moreover, by invoking muted oracles, Patterson firmly rooted his print epistemology in the visual metaphors (e.g.
hoodwinking ) and theatrical sensibilities so central to the Blavatsyian enterprise. Scandalous expos bleeds into the theatrics of exposure, and print enhances its reality effects through its appeal to the epistemologies of the eye. (Hodgson would later take up this interest in theatre, reporting on how Pierre Coulomb disguised himself as a Mahatma by donning a flowing muslin robe and an oversized prosthetic head with a turban, or fehta, on top).[438]
Patterson s expos drew on its wider colonial context to articulate its critique of Theosophy. For the better part of the nineteenth century, epistemologies of exposure similar to Patterson s had structured missionary attacks on Hinduism and Indian religions as a whole. Its guiding principle (analyzed at length in Chapter 2) bears repeating here: missionary writing about Hinduism proceeded from the belief that public speech about false religion undermines that religion, that to make Hinduism public to expose it is to undo Hinduism. The missionaries had sought to harness the press to curb superstition and other forms of false belief; they were, accordingly, aghast at the rise of Theosophy s offmodern heresy. As Anglican polemicist A. R. Fausset complained in 1885, Theosophy was not only preparing the way for bringing back the Oriental philosophies, metempsychosis, nature worship, [and] divination ; it was even a harbinger of the Antichrist.[439]
If Theosophy s occult sensibility alarmed theorists of modernity committed to an ethic of openness, it also allowed those theorists to amplify the alleged divide between modern and anti-modern, between East and West. For instance, amateur philologist and British Buddhist Arthur Lillie insisted that secrecy and its twin sister cunning were Oriental, childish and effeminate traits. If the Occult Brothers came out of their caves and mixed with mankind we should find them merely attenuated ascetics, inferior in matters of science, wisdom, and knowledge to the higher minds of our Western civilization. [440] Lillie leaves little doubt as to how the public sphere was rhetorically coded: the attenuated frames of ill-clad Orientals, once dragged into public, could not withstand the searing light of the scientific sun.
The Theosophists sought to rethink this paradigm. Although both Theosophical and anti-Theosophical polemics tended to align Theosophy with belief, sincerity, and spirituality, and its opponents with skepticism, cynicism, and materialism, Theosophy too wielded the freethinking liberationist values of the Enlightenment, and its skeptical ethic shaped its agenda from the start. As Blavatsky put it, the Theosophical Society was a pioneer of free thought and an uncompromising enemy of priestly and monkish fraud and despotism. [441] Similarly, in Olcott s November 1875 inaugural address, he proclaimed the nascent organization a force for critique. If I rightly apprehend our work, it is to aid in freeing the public mind of theological superstition and a tame subservience to the arrogance of science. [442] At war with ecclesiastical despots , the Theosophists would, like so many freethinkers before them, liberate the multitude of people of many different creeds worshipping, through sheer ignorance, shams and effete superstitions, and who are only waiting to be shown the audacity and dishonesty of their spiritual guides to call them to account and begin to think for themselves. [443]
Olcott s is a liberationist rhetoric that calls for the exposure of conniving and crafty priests so that the gullible multitude can be remade as a critical public. The cardinal difference between Olcott and (for example) Draper is that Olcott couples institutional science with institutional Christianity both deaden the critical capacities of the public, lulling their followers into a tame obedience. The Theosophical agenda was to free science of its dogmatic institutionalism so that, with a renewed empirical ethos, it could discover the palpability of the spiritual world. (Theosophy never contested the priority of the empirical in determining truth. Its occult worlds were built upon the primacy of experience as guarantor of correct knowledge).
Theosophists rancor towards ecclesiastical despots, however, consistently proved the more pungent, and its acridity only mounted on the mission field of India. Olcott s diary records several acrimonious encounters with Christian missionaries, such as the morning a few months after the Theosophists arrival in Bombay when a Methodist gray-bearded fanatic dropped in to convert us before breakfast. HPB squeezed him dry between the covers of her Josephus and Philo the Jew. [444] The
Society s anti-missionary rhetoric turned especially sour in the aftermath of the
Coulomb Affair. From the start, cries of missionary conspiracy marked the
Theosophical response to the Coulomb-Patterson letters, allegedly fabricated by what Damodar Mavalankar termed the clerical party. [445] Eventually the entire episode would simply be known as the notorious Madras Missionary Plot. [446] The Theosophists tapped into the anti-clerical imaginary that had lent shape to Patterson s expos in order to undercut the legitimacy of missionaries themselves. It was the missionary fable, and not the Theosophical one, that had been designed to hoodwink the public. 80
General H. R. Morgan s Reply to A Report of an Examination into the Blavatsky Correspondence by J.D.B. Gribble offers the richest elaboration of this motif. Morgan adopts the rhetoric of priestcraft and exposure and turns it on the missionaries here the Scottish Protestants become the quintessential crafty and self-serving clerics. Morgan repeatedly compares these Protestant missionaries to their Catholic nemeses, suggesting that they claim a near-papal infallibility[447] and comparing their impudent attempt to hoodwink the public to the machinations of the Jesuits. He goes so far as to draw a parallel between their moral stabbing of Madame Blavatsky and Inquisitorial modes of securing religious orthodoxy, such as torture with the rack. Morgan invokes Draper, emphatically situating the Madras missionaries within the long history of Christian suppression of scientific truth, and assures his readers that Draper s narrative provides the key to all the plots of the Padrees, including the present one. Even the Theosophical practice of terming all missionaries padrees following the usage common in Indian languages equates these Protestant Scots with their Latinate
Catholic opponents. [448]
Non-Christian religions were, however, typically spared the lash of the Theosophical tongue. Theosophy justified its dual position mocking Christianity, while defending Hinduism and other religions with an appeal to the occult laws of science. This strategy is articulated memorably by Morgan. Sardonically stacking miracle on miracle to delimit the bounds of the reasonably real, he insists that if these Padrees can ask the Hindoo to believe that Jonah was swallowed by a whale, and remained in his belly for three days and three nights, surely the Hindoo can ask the
Padree to believe that he has received a letter from a living Mahatma through the air! In this argument, the Mahatmas recede this discourse is more concerned with the itineraries of their precipitated letters. Morgan hitches his politics of the possible to the ultimate authority of science, asserting that the Mahatmas Theosophical-cumHindu wonders adhere to still-unknown natural laws, which, although seemingly wondrous to the modern mind, are nonetheless fully calculable and chastely scientific; biblical miracles, on the other hand, are, by any measure, patently absurd. [449] In a single polemic swoop, he dismisses the missionaries and reclaims scientific empiricism for a resurgent, rationalist Hinduism more modern than modern science itself.
In the end, what was most galling about the Theosophists to their opponents was perhaps not so much their apparent starry-eyed credulity, but their presumption to play Galileo and cast the rest of the callous Anglophone world as the medieval
Church. No wonder that Olcott, aboard a Rangoon-bound ship at the height of the
Coulomb Affair, wrote in his diary that the weather was lovely, but that the American Missionaries on board have the air of cads and bigots. There is something extremely petty and malicious about Missionaries when in our presence. [450]
If the epistemology of exposure, in its scientific, missionary, and Theosophical formations, promised absolute openness, the unlimited legibility of all phenomena to the reading public, it could never quite deliver. Reality consistently receded behind the veil of the page, and the public fact of the expos slipped into the irresolvable murk of scandal. I would argue that Blavatsky s writings explore an alternate model for the public sphere based on occluded, fragmentary knowledge. Her occult epistemology of the veil offers a more capacious frame for interpreting religious publics and public religions, and, in this, retains its appeal long after the controversies of the Coulomb Affair. In what follows, I sketch the curvatures of the public conjured by Blavatsky in Isis Unveiled.
Blavatsky never seems entirely at ease with the public that she courts. Despite her occasional sympathetic appeal to public judgment [451] or the bewildered public (IU, 1:x), Blavatsky generally refers to reading audiences with considerable ire, terming them the multitude (IU, 1:xliv) and the rabble (IU, 1:12) or dismissing the public as a docile and pious child that ever turns round with a timid look of adulation to see whether the nurse, old Mrs. Public Opinion, is satisfied (IU, 1:167). From the book s opening pages, Blavatsky garrisons herself against too free a public eye, disqualifying prominent public voices before they even have the chance to lambaste her work. For instance, at the end of the preface, she enumerates and derides the numerous classes likely to array themselves against us, including not only Christians and Scientists, but also Pseudo-Scientists, Broad Churchmen, Freethinkers, Men of Letters, and the
mercenaries and parasites of the Press (IU, 1:vii-viii).
Where the epistemology of exposure held that skeptical public speech faith s rendering an account of itself to reason deflates public fictions to produce public truths, Blavatsky s occult epistemology resists this logic. In fact, she goes so far as to suggest the opposite: skepticism can itself become a dogma that stymies the truths of the spirit, especially when co-opted by men of a materialist mindset. Tracing a genealogy from Kapila to Doubting Thomas to Voltaire, she aligns the forces of doubt with the dogmatism of the medieval Church the skeptics can no more succeed in checking the progress of truth than the ignorant bigots who sat in judgment over Galileo checked the progress of the earth s rotation (IU, 1:121). Blavatsky waxes especially wroth when chastising the [p]ositivists the mental sucklings of Auguste Comte, whose bosoms swell at the thought of plucking deluded humanity from the dark abyss of superstition and rebuilding the cosmos on improved principles (IU, 1:75). It is spiritualist skepticism alone that inherits the torch of truth, and it is spiritualist skepticism that will rebuild the cosmos; its materialist cousin can only deepen the abyss of superstitious delusion.
As Blavatsky sought to reclaim skepticism from the materialists, she also sought to reshape the contours of the public arena. Even she, with her esoteric sensibilities, could not entirely resist the imperatives of publicity; but she adapted the trope of exposure, with its skeptical ethos and liberationist rhetoric, so that it would inculcate desire for occult, never-quite-open knowledge. Blavatsky plies a richly layered striptease epistemology that, among other things, calls for the disrobing of crafty priests. For Blavatsky, the only real religion is religion in the nude: we must show our false theologies in their naked deformity, and distinguish between divine religion and human dogmas. Our voice is raised for spiritual freedom, and our plea made for enfranchisement from all tyranny, whether of SCIENCE or THEOLOGY (IU, 1:xlv). Her plea is for readers to scrutinize her theological and scientistic opponents, stripping their truth claims of all human deformities to reveal the naked truth that will set the public free.
But Blavatsky enjoins a doubled ethic of openness and concealment, locating the promise of divine knowledge in the movement between the two. The primary trope here is that of unveiling. The term implies a double movement: just as the veil seems to solicit its own removal, the unveiled always refers back to the veil that preceded and produced it. The naked truth, in the epistemology of the veil, is always posterior to the cloaked lie and dependent on it for its very being; public openness conceals the
closures from which it derives existence and meaning. All publics, occult and otherwise, stem from a process of un/veiling.[452]
Blavatsky deploys the veil in a variety of ways, beginning with her book s title.[453] Often Isis s veils are tangible and literal garments and curtains occluding bodies and spaces. At other times, they are more metaphorical. Of the latter, the most revealing veil in Isis is the veil of language it is jargon that occludes the truths of the secret doctrine (IU, 1:xliv). The greatest teachers of divinity agree that nearly all ancient books were written symbolically and in a language intelligible only to the initiated (IU, 1:19). Too many modern readers forget this. The phrases of the mediaeval alchemist they read literally; and even the veiled symbolology of Plato is commonly misunderstood by the modern scholar (IU, 1:37). Blavatsky s promise is to pull aside the veil of discourse that obscures the spiritual penumbrum of the Real. She will do this, first, by decoding the symbolology that cloaks ancient wisdom, so that the divine light can shine again in the modern age. Second, she will ensure that modern jargons do not replace the old: she vows to rescue real science and true religion from both the Bible of the clergy and scientists self-made Codex of possibilities in nature (IU, 1:xi). The divine and the natural converge for Blavatsky, both finding their proper domain in the sphere beyond language what Blavatsky calls the Unutterable (IU,
1:15).
Blavatsky s epistemology of the veil further entails a distinctly spatial imaginary. A veil divides one space into two, turning the here into the there. This trait is most apparent in Isis s myriad references to sanctuaries and temples in exotic locales, secreted away by impenetrable veils. I would suggest that the spatiality of the veil also structures Blavatsky s more mundane epistemological claims. For instance, when she claims that plants, stones, and other objects, in addition to their unremarkable outer being, possess a veiled but potent inner nature which has yet to be discovered, Blavatsky renders these ordinary objects exotic and inaccessible (IU, 1:466). The veil, perhaps above all else, ensures that the truth of the world is always just beyond our reach.
It is this tendency of the veil to postpone revelation, to push the divine to the outer limits of human geography, which lends to Blavatsky s topography of truth its emphatically Eastern orientation. Hers is an unabashed Orientalism, repopulating Asia with the West s every mystic fantasy, and it is India that anchors her occult Orient. While a few of the Masters (Cagliostro, le Comte de Saint-Germain) may have made their home in Europe, the majority of the planet s spiritual virtuosi reside in the colonies, not the metropole.
In key ways, Theosophy s phantom Mahatmas conflate the subaltern consciousness of the colonized with all that is occluded by the language of colonial modernity. [454] The allure of the Asiatic in some of Blavatsky s most important writings is
that he cannot speak or at least that he resides on the margins of speech, opening the portal to the Unutterable. When Koot Hoomi and Morya do speak, it is through Blavatsky as amanuensis. She credited large parts of Isis Unveiled to their astral hands, and attributed to them the many precipitated letters that miraculously descended on the Society over the years. There is perhaps no figure more characteristic of the Theosophical imaginary than the astral Asian, the only trace of whom is a fragmentary writing that derives its aura from his absence.[455]
These naked sons of the East (IU, 1:74) also orient Blavatsky s distinctive erotics. Isis Unveiled cultivates a longing for these men, but never on a blandly heterosexual model. Blavatsky s own dealings with gender were far to intricate for this this is a woman said to have spurned her Russian husband, fought in men s clothes alongside Garibaldi at Mentana, and otherwise flouted femininity. Even in her work as amanuensis for the Masters, she donned a masculine persona, rendering her public self a strange astral fusion of male and female perhaps this explains her authorial preference for the neuter HPB over the feminine Helena.
In any case, Blavatsky s epistemology of the veil appeals to a gendered imaginary to articulate desire for occluded knowledge. In one especially redolent passage from Isis Unveiled, Blavatsky describes first exploring the penetralia of [the East s] deserted sanctuaries :
Reverently we stepped in spirit within the temple of Isis; to lift aside the veil of
the one that is and was and shall be at Sais; to look through the rent curtain of
the Sanctum Sanctorum at Jerusalem; and even to interrogate within the crypts which once existed beneath the sacred edifice, the mysterious Bath-K l. The Filia Vocis the daughter of the divine voice responded from the mercy seat within the veil, and science, theology, every human hypothesis and conception born of imperfect knowledge, lost forever their authoritative character in our sight. (IU, 1:vi-vii)
What lies beyond human knowledge, in the Blavatskian imaginary, is the divine voice. It speaks from within the veil of sacred spaces located in the colonized East, and these spaces are typically feminized ( temple of Isis, daughter of the divine ). The epistemology of the veil implies the coquetry of the striptease, in which woman appears as the object of a Theosophical knowledge hungry for penetralia. Blavatsky inevitably unsettles gender binaries, but an aggressive erotics with a distinctly patriarchal tone does color her quest for occult knowledge. And her striptease epistemology often took on a still more menacing timbre in the hands of others, including, and perhaps especially, her critics. Edmund Garrett s 1894 pamphlet Isis Very
Much Unveiled: The Story of the Great Mahatma Hoax, for instance, promises to strip Blavatsky herself down before the peering public.[456] The sexual undertone to such criticisms was not lost on the Madame herself. As she quipped in a letter, [p]amphlets by Reverends, books and articles exposing me from top to foot appear every day. [457]
But an Isis very much unveiled can, perhaps, never quite compete with the allure of an Isis who delivers both concealment and exposure simultaneously. The success of Blavatsky s occult knowledge is in its realization that sometimes not knowing the truth is what the public craves most indeed, that it is the collective craving for elusive truth that causes people to cohere as a public.
I would argue that the veil s coquettish occlusion of public knowledge is as important a feature of the Theosophical effort to re-enchant the world as the phenomena themselves. Magical thinking can include not only concrete claims about the possibilities in nature, but also more general maxims about the limits of the knowable. Max Weber defined disenchantment as an Occidental historical process that, over the course of millennia, produced a modern condition wherein there are no mysterious incalculable forces that come into play, but rather that one can, in principle, master all things by calculation. [458] Blavatsky, by contrast, repeatedly thwarted calculability via occlusive veils thrown over the knowing eye.
To insist, however, that the appeal of Theosophy had nothing to do with its miracles is, surely, disingenuous. The Coulomb controversy erupted around the fabulous phenomena, and any responsible account of the scandal must make sense of these hotly contested miracles. In order to interpret the phenomena, I turn to a review of Theosophist A. P. Sinnett s 1881 The Occult World, written by Hargrave Jennings, the author of noted occult works like The Indian Religions, or Results of the Mysterious Buddhism (1858); The Rosicrucians, Their Rites and Mysteries (1870); and Phallic Miscellanies: Facts and
Phases of Ancient and Modern Sex Worship, as Illustrated Chiefly in the Religions of India (1891).
Jennings account of the modern public prefigures some aspects of Weber s disenchantment narrative: The now comfortable world has succeeded in a very difficult enterprise. It has got miracle out of the world after all the wriggling and twistings of miracle to keep here. Jennings claims that common-sense has got the better of delusion and superstition ; it has caused sensible men to exhale miracle, that uncomfortable thing, and replace it with a robust sense of self-satisfied selfpossession. [459] In the modern world, everything is natural. Man is so very natural. Nature is so very natural. Everything is so really real. We only think strange thoughts when we are not right (OWR, 15). The comfort of this calculable world is secured by the bourgeois tastemakers of the day. Jennings reviles reviewers for publications like the Athenaeum and the Saturday Review, who, with grand-motherly care, guard the pabulum of the great reading public so that it can have its quiet nights, untroubled by the eruption of realities beyond its borders (OWR, 18).
Jennings lauds Sinnett s very uncomfortable book for dislodging the public from its pabulum. It opens a rift in the fabric of the real, a crinkle in the conservative status quo. Despite Jennings own apparent faith that empirical investigation will confirm Sinnett s claims, he too stumbles over the gap between miracle and report, between event and representation. Although he wants to affirm the reality of Sinnett s occult miracles, he can only do so with words that enjoy no more priority in the public mind that anyone else s. And so, Jennings introduces a key incalculability into the realm of the spirit: These questions [of the authenticity of miracle] are by no means settled by persiflage. They are rather intensified except in the minds of fools by such a process. Ridicule will never kill this difficulty in supernaturalism. It only makes us melancholy (OWR, 20). The profusion of skeptical claims cannot banish miracle; it can only incite more speech. One might suggest that, for Jennings, miracle is that which lies beyond discourse; the Real that eludes the symbolic order founded on the absence of signified objects; Blavatsky s Unutterable. Persiflage, in Jennings theory, is excitable speech that chases miracle, trying to fix it in language a hopeless task.
This is surely why Franz Hartmann s complaint about Gribble s handwriting analysis seems to sum up so much of the Coulomb Affair: I cannot follow him through all his dexterous and intricate vermiculations. [460] The profusion of discourse about the phenomena misses the point wonders always exceed the capacity of linguistic signs to represent them, and the allure of the phenomena stemmed in part from this constitutive gap between spectacle (tingling bells, plummeting roses, surfacing teacups, floating heads) and scandal (the stuff of language, gossip and print media). The alleged contest between belief and doubt at play in the Coulomb Affair took its shape from the jump-cut between the bounded public that can witness a spectacular miracle and the potentially unbounded public that can discuss it, from the transmutation of momentary magic into the black fact of ink.
The Society for Psychical Research ran afoul of a parallel problem. Science, in
the Coulomb Affair, found itself wallowing in very unscientific gossip. Herbert Stack complained that the committee s investigation of Blavatsky looked something like evaluating the miracles at Lourdes by asking a Roman Catholic for a second-hand account of them.[461] He differentiated between two methods of investigation the judicial and the experimental, and complained that the Blavatsky investigations relied almost exclusively on the former.[462] Moreover, Stack suggests that republishing these tall tales will only give the stamp of our silent approval to them. [463] Persiflage the circulation of discourse confirms miracle as social fact. Only the palpability of the experimental method can quash miracle.
According to Jennings, however, not even sensible contact with miracle, face to face experience of the thing itself, can convince the realist and the doubter : a miracle to stay is impossible. The reason is that everything preternatural must, in the nature of things, be only interjectionary. It comes and it goes (OWR, 20). The promised plenitude of the occultists is a ruse. It can never be attained, as the nature of things dictates that the preternatural must pass: miracle is inherently evanescent. A miracle that stays would become mundane, routinized.[464] Jennings is a melancholy philosophy the ultimate object of public desire will always, by its very nature, remain beyond public reach, and persiflage can only inflame the public s occult longings but, I would venture, he means it as a critical melancholia.[465]
Miracle, even and perhaps especially in absentia, rouses the public from its pabulum. Its insistent wriggling along the limit of the real can, perhaps, press upon the comfortable world at its point of maximum contradiction, rending new openings in the politics of the possible.[466] If we follow Weber s formula, by disrupting the British public s ability to calculate the world, miracle would also have disrupted the British ability to master that world.
Damodar Mavalankar offered what seems the best articulation of Theosophy s wistful promise: Happy would be that day indeed when the noumenal will supersede the phenomenal. [467] Numinous miracle recedes behind the veil of Blavatsky s notoriously dubious phenomena, refusing to stay in the public arena. The miracle public, conjured by event and gossipy aftermath, coheres around this wondrous absence and the blandishments of the veil. No matter how ardent the expos , the miracle will never quite open. It just wriggles.
As Koot Hoomi
once observed, for a fact to be received as such, it must first have become
[a person s] own property, have proved amenable to their own modes of
investigation. The fact is a domesticated event. A miracle is something both
more resistant and more productive. As the Mahatma reminds us, for nearly two
thousand years countless milliards have pinned their faith upon the testimony
of one hysterical woman regarding Jesus ascension into heaven and, according
to Koot Hoomi, this woman was not overly trustworthy. [468]
It is, it would seem, precisely the ambiguity of her testimony, its
peverformativity, that secured its universal appeal. If we are to understand
Blavatsky as a skeptic s medium, her ultimate lesson is this: more powerful
than the fact or the lie is the tale that confounds the two.
CONCLUSION:
Credulity is not faith. Credulity is an obstacle which prevents true faith to take root in the hearts of men; the world must pass through a stage of unbelief to arrive at a place where belief can be united with reason.
Eliphas Levi, The Theosophist (1885) [469]
Thus have we traced the history of priestcraft to colonial India. The imposture theory of religion may have received its most influential articulation during the
Enlightenment, at the hands of polemical writers like Charles Blount and Bernard le Boivier de Fontenelle. But insofar as priestcraft and imposture provided the conceptual apparatus for a truly secularist skepticism, they came to do so at a later date, and under the shadow of empire. As William Howitt discovered when writing his Popular History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations in the winter of 1832, priestcraft led ineluctably to India, where (as he put it) the powers of the priest were at once in full flower and full fruit. After completing his History, Howitt began to protest the imperial excesses of British rule in India, but not the fact of empire itself; he hoped for a more ethical empire, an empire that would cultivate the moral constitution of its subjects by promoting what I have termed anticlerical modernity. That is to say that during the nineteenth century, imperial power came to promulgate doubt, centering its effort to reform India on the criticism of religion.
By suggesting that modernity should be understood as anticlerical rather than strictly secular, I have tried to rethink the relation of modernity to religion. In anticlerical modernity, religious and secular critics of sacerdotal authority enter into a tactical alliance, such that the doctrinal difference between the two is often obscured by their shared rhetoric of priestly fraud. Classical narratives of secularization obscure the complexities of these strategic alliances by granting priority to the irreligious critics. One of the objectives of this dissertation has been simple historical corrective: Karl Marx and William Howitt intervened in the imposture theory of religion at roughly the same time, and despite its disproportionate influence, Marx s materialist theory of false belief did not supersede Howitt s Quaker theory of priestcraft. Rather, the continued interplay of these two coeval modes of traducing religion is what produced the characteristic cultural forms of anticlerical modernity. In making this argument, I have followed the lead of historians like Justin Champion and Mark Goldie who have tried to abide by on John Toland s noted early modern maxim: religion s safe, with priestcraft is the war.
My foray into the history of priestcraft has been distinctive, however, in its attention to the cultural crosscurrents of the colonial encounter. I have tried to demonstrate that the concept anticlerical modernity lends itself well to what Edward Said termed contrapuntal analysis : sidelining secularism allows nineteenth-century Indian critics of religion to lay claim to the making of a modernity that might otherwise exclude them on the basis of belief. As I have argued, the intimate enmities of colonialism pushed anticlerical modernity into the interstitial spaces of empire, forcing its paranoid fantasies of priestly deception into culturally hybrid zones and so allowing for its critical re-inscription from within the Hindu fold.
It was within this expanded colonial field that priestcraft came to be resituated, reconfigured, and even remade. The chapters of this dissertation have noted, in turn, the complicity of the imposture theory of religion with the diffuse field of imperial power (Chapter 2); the critical positions opened up within Hindu devotion by the juridical application of this theory (Chapter 3); how a tendentious Hindi translation of priestcraft intervened into philosophical debates about the ontology of illusion (Chapter 4); and how colonial occultism tried to thwart the epistemology of exposure and its promise of public certainty (Chapter 5). In its colonial redeployment priestcraft came to abut Indic imaginaries of religious illusion, ranging from folkloric spoofs of gurus authority to bhakti poetics to Vedantic philosophy. While it may have seemed that the colonial context had distorted anticlerical modernity, this was not the case. Rather, colonialism revealed constitutive contradictions that had structured modernity even in its metropolitan locations. Colonial India thus provides an ideal setting for considering the ambiguities of modernity at large. While the chapters of this dissertation detail many such ambiguities, four in particular bear repeating here.
First, as Howitt s hope for an ethical empire suggests, by the 1830s the problem of priestcraft had become entangled with a form of governmentality that ruled populations by managing the moral constitution of individual subjects. Doubly fueled by Evangelical fire and Utilitarian reason, this pastoral power generally went by the name of reform, and it rose to prominence more or less simultaneously in both Britain and India. Especially in the latter, a central plank of the reformist platform was the annihilation of corrupt priestly authority. In the colony, however, the critical demolition of traditional authority figures often did less to establish the bourgeois egalitarianism enjoined by liberal political theory than to enhance the quasi-magical authority of the imperial state itself. Critics of religion thus found themselves in a double bind, wherein both doubt and belief had immediate political implications, as the contest between religion and modernity came to replicate the conflict between colonized and colonizer. The realm of culture did not, however, simply serve as a neutral site for the enactment of a displaced politics. In its displacement, the political assumed new shape. The polemic pliability of priestcraft thus allowed a range of public actors to re-imagine the contours of anticlerical modernity.
Second, the colonial context highlights the degree to which belief is by its very nature oriented to the outside, to the social, legal, and cultural networks that situate the believing subject. Two modalities of belief were predominant during the period:
propositional belief (i.e. cognitive assent) and relational belief (i.e. loving trust). The former mode was more prevalent in the official Anglophone arenas of court and press and was more readily assimilated to the bureaucratic Hinduism that emerged under colonial rule. The affective intensities of the latter, meanwhile, instantiated social bonds, founded the devotional askesis of bhakti, and ultimately proved resistant to the drama of priestly exposure often enacted by critics of religion. If colonial governmentality had rendered belief political by attempting to regulate its alleged excesses, India s credulous natives made good use of this shift in the field of power; believing cannily and critically, they used religion to intervene in the micropolitics of colonial rule.
Third, the material culture of print was of central importance to the rhetoric of
priestcraft in India, as elsewhere. While critics of false religion promised the full exposure of priestly charlatans, all they could deliver were expos s. Especially in matters of miracle, these only further submerged public knowledge in the ambiguities of belief in rumor, gossip, hearsay, faith, trust, and the fiduciary. Priestly rule was often contrasted with the social order instituted by the free press. This classically liberal narrative was undergirded by a jubilant technological determinism: the press was the juggernaut of liberal modernity, crushing despotic priests under the unstoppable wheel of deliberative democracy. If apologists of print tended to overlook the medium s ability to re-enchant the world with new forms of mystery and devotion, they also tended to downplay the degree to which the freedoms of the print public were guaranteed and overseen by the colonial state. Libel law was particularly pertinent for critics of religious imposture, who were always at risk of allowing their denunciations of universal priestcraft to descend into the personal defamation of actual priests. To write the history of colonial priestcraft is thus to write the history of the colonial public or rather, of the labyrinthine, dynamic formations of public and private, the confusion of which proved so culturally and politically productive in colonial India.
Fourth, the cultural contiguities produced by priestcraft in its polemic circulation highlight conceptual problems endemic to the imposture theory of religion. Mark Goldie has shown how the imposture theory promises that the unmasking of nefarious charlatans will produce a disenchanted world ridded forever of illusion. This redemptive narrative was, as he suggests, at the heart of Karl Marx s theory of ideology: the overthrow of priestcraft would allow the duped to abandon delusory flowers and see their real chains. Likewise, I have discussed how Swami Dayanand Saraswati sought to deliver Hinduism from the frauds of Indian popes, paving the way for a confidently empiricist Hindu science by staving off all worldly illusion. In the process, however, Dayanand had to reckon with the philosophical legacy of Shankara, who theorized illusion (maya) as that which constitutes the material world and the human subjects within it. Despite his best efforts, Dayanand s disenchanted Hinduism remained haunted by the Vedantic possibility that fake flowers are all we have, that illusion is the horizon of the real. One might suggest that this position anticipates the more sophisticated theory of ideology to emerge in later Marxist thought. Rather than promising deliverance from illusion, this M!y!v!d$ Marxism takes illusion to be constitutive of human subjectivity per se. If these two very different bodies of thought seem to share a set of conceptual topoi, this is no coincidence. Both respond to the same foundational rhetoric of priestly imposture and intervene in the same anticlerical modernity.
Extending the history of colonial priestcraft past 1885 would surely prove fruitful. Indeed, as the anti-colonial movement emerged, it became apparent that colonialism had amplified the political potential and political risks of charismatic religious authority. M. K. Gandhi s career could be analyzed as a performative exploration of the place of the priest Indian politics. As Ashis Nandy has noted, Gandhi s iconicity derives from his skillful inversion of colonial ideology s most beloved binaries. Where the half-clad fakir had been relegated by the British to the dustbin of the apolitically religious past, Gandhi thrust the fakir to the forefront of history.[470] In
doing so, however, he ran afoul of the secularist refusal of charismatic authority. Bipin Chandra Pal, for instance, decried Gandhi s great hold on the masses. By reviving medieval religious sentiments, he had endangered the Indian democracy to come by smothering the people s freedom of thought with the dead weight of unreasoning reverence. [471] Gandhi, with his pontifical authority, had led the people in faith blindfolded. [472] Thus was priestcraft reinstated as the very condition of mass politics.
Pal and Gandhi came to inhabit the narrative of priestly imposture, transporting the hoary conflict among skeptic, charlatan, and multitude into a novel political milieu. In many ways, Pal s criticism of Gandhi prefigures the postcolonial debate about the constitutive contradictions of Indian secularism. Pal, the Anglophone skeptic, foresees the danger of a vernacular politics forged through the medieval bond of religious belief. Gandhi, well aware of the charge of charlatanism, sought to retrieve charisma as a political form and indeed to amplify it by means of the mass media, his iconic authority constituted as much through the circulation of images as through his own embodied practice. Gandhi s pontifical authority primed the constitutive contradictions of the political concept of the people, hemmed in by liberal autonomy, religious electorates, and societal influence. [473]
Alongside its imbrication with the political forms of nationalism, the problematic of priestcraft has also inflected an important Indian contribution to global public culture: cosmopolitan guru English. [474] Take, for instance, the case of Osho (a.k.a. Bhagwan Shree Rajneesh). Born in 1931 in what is now Madhya Pradesh, Osho rose to international notoriety due less to his spiritual sagacity than to his worldly lan. He was famous for his mammoth collection of Rolls Royces and Rolexes; his intoxicating blend of sex and power; and his facility in Indian and Western philosophy ( Osho, for example, is a contraction of William James oceanic experience ).[475] Less noted is Osho s expertise in the imposture theory of religion.
In his provocatively titled Priests and Politicians: The Mafia of the Soul, Osho recounts an ancient story in which one devil assures another that humanity will never see through their demonic delusions. As the devil explains,
The priests are my people. They have already surrounded the man who found the truth. Now they will become the mediators between the man of truth and the masses. They will raise temples, they will write scriptures, they will interpret and distort everything. They will ask people to worship, to pray. And in all this hubbub, the truth will be lost. This is my old method which has always succeeded.
According to Osho, religion needs no mediators. Priests fabricated their otherworldly fiction to propagate a life-denying asceticism. Osho, a guru in the tradition of Marx and Nietzsche, vows to deliver man to himself by repealing the decrees of the worldhating clerics.8 Osho rails against organized religions, plying a hedonistic creed tailored to the consumer desires of spiritual individuals. Priestly institutions, he avers, mix the religious and the political: priests are simply politicians, wolves hiding themselves in the skin of sheep. They should, Osho tells us, drop this mask of being religious and disappear from the world. [476] Pure religion renounces political life entirely for solitary spirituality and the personal quest for pleasure. Although Osho is generally interpreted as an exemplar of guru autocracy, of priestcraft in full fruit and full flower, his teachings take up priestcraft theory and bring it to its logical conclusion:
his radically privatized religion is fully consonant with the libidinal economy of consumer capitalism.[477] As Osho presents himself, he and Rajiv Gandhi (to whom this essay is addressed) want the same thing: Gandhi wants to get religion out of politics, and Osho wants politics out of religion.
Rather than the utter atrophy of religion, secular modernity demands that religion be reformed that it permit the emergence of a bourgeois social order by excising its sacred hierarchies and policing the boundary between the transcendent divine and the material world. It has often accomplished this by identifying and unmasking of priestly enchanters. As I have suggested, the suspicion of religion has been paradigmatic for modernity s hermeneutics of suspicion more broadly. The pervasive mistrust of wily priests institutes a habitus of paranoia, an all-consuming skepticism that can only end by returning to the powers of belief. This return can take many forms. In closing this dissertation, I would like to consider how skepticism has become conflated in some circles with one such structure of belief: the fiduciary web of the secular.
By some accounts, Edward Said organized his career around the notion secular criticism. [478] Indeed, in William D. Hart s estimation, he reinstates the Marxist maxim that the criticism of religion is the premise of all criticism.[479] As Said defined it, secular criticism is inherently oppositional and thus irreducible to any doctrine or political position. What it opposes is the religious, which Said defines as an agent of closure, shutting off human investigation, criticism, and effort in deference to the authority of the more-than-human, the supernatural, the otherworldly. [480] The quintessential example of a religious discourse on this model is Orientalism, as analyzed in Said s influential monograph of that name.[481] The task of criticism is to pit the secular against the religious so as to erode the latter s totalities. As Said explains, in its suspicion of totalizing concepts, in its discontent with reified objects, in its impatience with guilds, special interests, imperialized fiefdoms, and orthodox habits of mind, criticism is most itself and, if the paradox can be tolerated, most unlike itself at the moment it starts turning into organized dogma.
The paradox of Said s secular criticism is that it is founded in a dogmatic maxim: always oppose the religious. Doubt in its pure form is a negative capacity, an absolute refusal. Ever coy, it declines to join causes, delighting instead in the vagrant mobility of
perpetual dissent. But this last commitment, insofar as it is a commitment, is an intimation of something else; this is the trace of faith that skepticism can never dispense with. Secular criticism thus betrays itself in the very moment of its inception.
Jacques Derrida has termed this trace the fiduciary (see Introduction). As he explains, Enlightenment of tele-technoscientific critique and reason can only suppose trustworthiness. For Derrida, the fundamental human activity is the testimonial address of the other; this address relies on a fundamental communicative trust and on inter-subjective dependence. In order for the techno-scientific order to establish itself, it must appeal to this irreducible faith, which cements the social bond. In Derrida s words, the secular order always brings into play and confirms the fiduciary credit of an elementary faith which is, at least in its essence or calling, religious. The religious thus represents the internal limit to secular reason.[482] It follows that the skeptic must always, in order to remain a coherent subject sustained by a social order, rejoin the realm of the fiduciary: the moment of mistrust cannot last forever. If it did, the result would be paranoid psychosis.[483] The close kinship between faith and sociality is most evident in what I have been calling relational belief, the loving trust binding guru and devotee. As Terry Eagleton put it recently, faith is not primarily a belief that something or someone exists but rather a commitment and allegiance ; because it is constitutively social, orienting the subject in the world, faith is what animates political commitments.[484]
In other words, it is faith that drives Said s anti-colonial project. That insight, however, does not quite get at the function of the secular in Saidian criticism. If that word simply denotes a critical attitude, why attach it to criticism at all? By Said s account, isn t the phrase secular criticism redundant? What is the function of this strangely superfluous modifier, and why does it attach itself so insistently to the capacity for critical skeptical thought? I would suggest that, in laying claim to skepticism, secularism renders itself what Said would call a religious discourse. It settles into an orthodox habit of mind, an agent of closure, a reified conceptual object. This is demonstrated by the way that secularism constitutes its shadows : skepticism, tolerance, progress, liberty, democracy, the public sphere, etc.[485] When skepticism toward religion is entered onto this ledger, it comes to imply faith in its fellow terms; the secular modern social order becomes doubt s secret stowaway. That such secularist faith can become fully fundamentalist, one need look no farther than the New Atheism. This breed of best-selling screed decries religion as delusion, using hoary tropes of imposture to structure a skepticism with firm faith in the secular status quo.[486]
But even in the hands of much more agreeable writers, secularism has a way of subsuming rambunctious heterodoxies and restless skepticisms into its own dogmatic agenda.[487]
In this dissertation, I have tried to use religion to look askance at modernity.
Sumathi Ramasway has distilled this mode of criticism with the term off-modern. [488]
One might follow her lead and advocate for an off-secular criticism of religion that, in Dispesh Chakrabarty s formula, takes the secular to be both indispensible and inadequate for critical thought. While the secular remains indispensible in conceiving the critical capacity, it is also inadequate in canvassing the critical possibilities of religion. Aamir Mufti has tried to reformulate Said s secular criticism so that it does just this. As Mufti explains, secular criticism is first and foremost a practice of unbelief. Although it does target religion, it is aimed at secular beliefs as well, and, at its most ambitious, at all those moments at which thought and culture become frozen, congealed, thing-like, and self-enclosed hence the significance for [Said] of Luk cs s notion of reification. [489] Mufti proposes the term critical secularism to suggest the critical engagement with secularism itself. [490] Gauri Viswanathan has likewise intervened in Saidian secular criticism with her recommendation that scholars rethink secularism through the framework of heterodoxy. After all, religion as an oppositional knowledge system has excelled at criticism throughout history.[491] One of the virtues of Viswanathan s notion of heterodoxy is the way in which it resists secularist prolepsis; if Amartya Sen reads pre-modern heterodoxies as prefiguring deliberative democracy, Viswanathan attempts to subordinate the latter to the more capacious and surprising history of religious dissent.
It is this latter approach that has guided this dissertation s inquiry into anticlerical modernity. From William Howitt to Karsandas Mulji to Dayanand Saraswati to Helena Blavatsky, I have tried to chart the off-secular criticism of religion and its relation to British colonialism. Indeed, I have meant the notion of anticlerical modernity to be off-secular in just this sense. It engages the history of secularism by foregrounding religious critics of religion (Howitt alongside Marx); and it insists that anticlericalism be located at the interstices of empire, as the full sway of sacerdotalism can only be understood in global perspective (Dayanand alongside Luther).
To conclude, the history of anticlericalism relocates doubt to the fiduciary arena of interpersonal faith. It allows skeptics to refuse not only propositions, but also relationships. What it does not do, or at least not well enough, is to account for the critical powers of assent. Many theorists, from Saba Mahmood to Alain Badiou, have tried to recuperate the critical potential of religion. Faith and piety are, we have come to learn, the stuff of politics. But what fewer theorists have stopped to consider is the enduring appeal of the ersatz sacred, of religious phenomena that command belief precisely because they sit uneasily at the margins of plausibility and modernity. As Marcel Gauchet has suggested, religious belief is at bottom not only about assent but also, and perhaps more fundamentally, about refusal. The religious, he writes, is the principle of mobility placed in the service of inertia, it is the principle of transformation mobilized to protect the inviolability of things, it is the power of negation wholly redirected toward accepting and renewing the established law. [492]
In other words, religion serves up a heady mix of belief and doubt, trust and suspicion, acceptance and refusal. This is what makes faith different from knowledge. This is also what makes the ambiguous figure of the charlatan so compelling: he or she invites all of these things simultaneously by promising to deliver both truth and falsehood, each embedded in the other. If belief owes its force to the structural possibility that it will be betrayed by some perverse parody of the sacred, just as doubt owes its force to the possibility that it will be belied by faith, then it is no wonder that the charlatan has emerged as the major mediator between the two.
ARCHIVAL:
Olcott, Henry Steel. Diary. Microfilm Section, Nehru Memorial Library, New Delhi.
Papers Relating to the Investigation of Madame Blavatsky, Archives of the Society for Psychical Research, Cambridge University Library, Cambridge.
Records of Elphinstone College, Maharashtra State Archives, Elphinstone College, Mumbai.
NEWSPAPERS AND PERIODICALS:
Bombay Gazette
Bombay Saturday Review
Bombay Times and Courier
Bombay Times and Journal of Commerce
Boston Evening Transcript
Dnyanodaya (Bombay)
Graphic (London)
Liverpool Mercury
Madras Christian College Magazine
Madras Mail
Madras Times
Missionary Register
Oriental News (Bombay)
Poona Observer
Preston Guardian
Rast Goftar tatha Satya Prakash (Bombay)
Satya Mitra tatha Hakha Mazdayasannam (Bombay)
South Australian Register (Adelaide)
Stree Bodh (Bombay)
Telegraph and Courier (Bombay)
The Theosophist (Madras)
Times of India (Bombay)
OTHER SOURCES:
Adcock, Catherine. Religious Freedom and Political Culture: The Arya Samaj in Colonial North India. Ph.D. diss., University of Chicago, 2007.
Ahmad, Naheed Fatima. A History of Elphinstone College, 1827-1890: A Case Study in the Early Formation of an English-Educated Intelligentsia in Bombay. Ph.D. diss., Oxford University, 1982.
Anderson, Abraham, trans. The treatise of the three impostors and the problem of
Enlightenment : a new translation of the Trait des trois imposteurs (1777 edition). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism. London: Verso, 1991.
Anderson, Perry. Lineages of the Absolutist State. London: NLB, 1974.
Aravamudan, Srinivas. Guru English: South Asian Religion in a Cosmopolitan Language. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006.
Asad, Talal. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianity and Islam. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993.
--- . Reading a Modern Classic: W. C. Smith's The Meaning and End of Religion, History of Religions 40.3 (2001): 205-22.
--- . Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003.
Ashcraft, Richard. Anticlericalism and authority in Lockean political thought. In The Margins of Orthodoxy: Heterodox Writing and Cultural Response, 1660-1750, edited by Roger D. Lund, 73-96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1995).
Austin, J. L. How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975.
Babb, Lawrence A. and Susan S. Wadley, eds., Media and the Transformation of Religion in South Asia. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1995.
Balagangadhara, S. N. The Heathen in his Blindness : Asia, the West, and the Dynamic of Religion. Leiden: Brill, 1994.
Banerjee, Sumanta. The Parlour and the Streets: Elite and Popular Culture in Nineteenth Century Calcutta. Calcutta: Seagull Books, 1989.
Barz, Richard. The Bhakti Sect of Vallabhacarya. New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1992 [1976].
Bayley, C. A. Empire and Information: Intelligence Gathering and Social Communication in India, 17801870. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Beckerlegge, Gwilym, ed. Colonialism, Modernity, and Religious Identities: Religious Reform Movements in South Asia. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Bennett, Peter. The Path of Grace: Social Organization and Temple Worship in a Vai%!ava Sect. Delhi: Hindustan Publishing Company, 1993.
Bentley, John. Essays Relative to the Habits, Character, and Moral Improvement of the Hindoos London: Kingsbury, Parbury, and Allen, 1823.
Berti, Sylvia, Fran oise Charles-Daubert, and Richard H. Popkin, eds. Heterodoxy,
Spinozism, and Free Thought in Early-Eighteenth-Century Europe: Studies on the Trait des
Trois Imposteurs. Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996.
Bhabha, Homi. The Location of Culture. New York: Routledge, 1994).
Bhargava, Rajeev, ed. Secularism and its Critics. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Birwood, George ed. The Stree Bodh and Social Progress in India: A Jubilee Memorial. Bombay: The Stree Bodh Office, 1908.
Blavatsky, H. P. Isis Unveiled. Edited by Boris de Zirkoff. 2 vols. Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2006 [1877].
Blount, Charles. Anima Mundi, or, An historical narration of the opinions of the ancients concerning man s soul after this life. London: Will Cademan, 1679.
--- . Great is Diana of the Ephesians, Or the Original of Idolatry. London: n. p., 1680.
--- . The Oracles of Reason, in Several Letters to Mr. Hobbs and Other Persons of Eminent Quality. London: n. p., 1693.
Boym, Svetlana. The Future of Nostalgia. New York: Basic Books, 2001.
Brown, Wendy. Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006.
Bryant, Edwin F., trans. Krishna: The Beautiful Legend of God: Srimad Bhagavata Purana, Book X. London: Penguin, 2003.
Bryant, Jacob. A New System; or, Analysis of Antient Mythology: wherein an attempt is made to divest tradition of fable, and to reduce the truth to its original purity. 6 vols. London: J. Walker, 1807 [1774-76].
Burger, Maya. The Hindu Model of Social Organization and the Bhakti Movement: The example of Vallabha s Sampradaya. In Devotional Literature in South Asia: Current Research, 1985-1988, edited by R. S. McGregor. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992.
Byrne, Peter. Natural Religion and the Nature of Religion: The Legacy of Deism. New York: Routledge, 1989.
Carlson, Maria. No Religion Higher Than Truth : A History of the Theosophical Movement in Russia, 1875-1922. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Carrette, Jeremey R. and Richard King. Selling Spirituality: The Silent Takeover of Religion. New York: Routledge, 2005.
Carter, Mia and Barbara Harlow. Archives of Empire. Vol. 1, From the East India Company to the Suez Canal. Durham: Duke University Press, 2003.
Carter-Ruck, Peter Frederick. Libel and Slander. Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 1973.
Casanova, Jos . Public Religions in the Modern World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.
Cassirer, Ernst. The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. Vol. 2, Mythical Thought. Translated by Ralph Mannheim. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1955.
Certeau, Michel de. The Possession at Loudun. Translated by Michael B. Smith. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
Cervantes, Fernando. The Devil in the New World: The Impact of Diabolism in New Spain. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994.
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. The Death of History?: Historical Consciousness and the Culture of Late Capitalism. Public Culture 4.2 (1992): 52-53.
--- . Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000.
Chatterjee, Mohini. Qualifications of Chelaship. The Theosophist, September 1884, 281283.
Chatterjee, Partha. Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse?. London: Zed Books, 1986.
--- . The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Champion, Justin. The Pillars of Priestcraft Shaken: The Church of England and its Enemies, 1660-1730. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
--- . Religion s Safe, with Priestcraft is the War: Augustan Anticlericalism and the
Legacy of the English Revolution, 1660-1720. The European Legacy 5.4 (2000): 547-561.
Chidester, David. Savage Systems: Colonialism and Comparative Religion in Southern Africa. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1996.
--- . Authentic Fakes: Religion and American Popular Culture. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005).
Collapse of Koot Hoomi An Incident in the Early History of Theosophy in India. London, Madras, and Colombo: Christian Literature Society, 1904.
Collier, Jeremy. A Short View of the Immorality and Profaneness of the English Stage. 2nd ed. London: Kable, Sare, and Hindmarsh, 1698.
Connoly, William E. Why I am not a Secularist. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000.
Copley, Antony. Religions in conflict: ideology, cultural contact, and conversion in late-colonial India. Delhi and New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.
--- , ed. Gurus and their Followers: New Religious Reform Movements in Colonial India. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Cox, Jeffrey. Imperial Fault Lines: Christianity and Colonial Power in India, 1818-1914. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000.
Dalmia, Vasudha and Heinrich von Stietencron. Representing Hinduism: The Construction of Religious Traditions and National Identity. New Delhi: Sage Publications, 1995.
Davenport, Richard A. Sketches of Imposture, Deception, and Credulity. London: Thomas Tegg and Sons, 1837.
Davidson, Allan K. Evangelicals and Attitudes to India, 1786-1813: Missionary publicity and Claudius Buchanan. Appleford, Abingdon, Berkshire: Sutton Courtenay Press, 1990.
Day!nand Saraswat$, Mahar(i. Saty"rth Prak"# (Dill$: %rya Pariw!r Yojn!, 2007 [1875]).
--- . Autobiography of Dayanand Saraswati, Swami. The Theosophist, October 1879, 913.
--- . Autobiography of Dayanand Saraswati, Swami The Theosophist, December 1879, 66-68.
--- . Autobiography of Dayanand Saraswati, Swami The Theosophist, November 1880, 24-26.
Dawkins, Richard. The God Delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2006.
Dennett, Daniel. Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking, 2006.
Derrida, Jacques. Margins of Philosophy. Translated by Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.
--- . Faith and Knowledge. Translated by Sam Weber. In Acts of Religion, ed. Gil Anijdar, 40-101. New York: Routledge, 2002.
--- . Hostipitality. Translated by Gil Anijdar. In Acts of Religion, ed. Gil Anijdar, 356-420. New York: Routledge, 2002.
Desai, A. R. Social Background of Indian Nationalism. Bombay: Popular Prakashan, 1976 [1948].
Dirks, Nicholas. Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of Modern India. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001.
--- . The Scandal of Empire: India and the Creation of Imperial Britain. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2006.
Dixon, Joy. Theosophy and Feminism in England. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 2001.
Dobbin, Christine. Urban Leadership in Western India: Politics and Communities in Bombay City 1840-1885. London: Oxford University Press, 1972.
Draper, John William. History of the Conflict between Religion and Science. 8th ed. New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1878 [1874].
Dubuisson, Daniel. The Western Construction of Religion: Myths, Knowledge, and Ideology.
Translated by William Sayers. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003.
Duff, Alexander. India and India Missions: Including Sketches of the Gigantic System of Hinduism, Both in Theory and Practice. 2nd ed. Edinburgh: John Johnstone, 1840.
During, Simon. Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2002,
Eachard, John. Grounds and Occasions of the Contempt of the Clergy and Religion Enquired Into. London: W. Godbid, 1670.
Eagleton, Terry. Ideology: An Introduction. London: Verso, 1991.
--- . Reason, Faith, and Revolution: Reflections on the God Debate. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2009.
Embree, Ainslee. Charles Grant and the British Rule in India. London: G. Allen, 1962.
Farquhar, John Nichol. Modern Religious Movements in India. New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1977 [1914].
Fausset, A. R. Spiritualism Tested by Scripture. London: Church of England Book Society, 1885.
Figueira, Dorothy Matilda. Aryans, Jews, Brahmins: Theorizing Authority through Myths of Identity. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2002.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. The Ideology of Religious Studies. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.
--- . Discourse on Civility and Barbarity: A Critical History of Religion and Related Categories. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Focus on: Vallabha Sampradaya. Journal of Vaisnava Studies 1:4 (1993).
Fontenelle, Bernard le Boivier de. Histoire des oracles. Edited by Louis Maigron. Paris: E. Corn ly, 1908.
Foucault, Michel. Nietzsche, Genealogy, History, in Language, Counter-Memory, Practice:
Selected Essays and Interviews, trans. Donald F. Bouchard and Sherry Simon, ed. Donald F. Bouchard, 139-164. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977.
--- . The Subject and Power. In Michel Foucault, Power, ed. James D. Faubion, 326-348. New York: New Press, 2000.
Freitag, Sandria. Collective Action and Community: Public Arenas in the Emergence of Communalism in North India. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1990.
--- , ed. Aspects of the Public in Colonial South Asia. Spec. issue of South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 14.1 (1991).
Frykenberg, Robert. Christianity in India: From Beginnings to the Present. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Frykenberg, Robert and Alaine Low, eds. Christians and Missionaries in India: Cross-Cultural Communication since 1500, with special reference to caste, conversion, and colonialism. Grand Rapids, MI. : W.B. Eerdmans, 2003.
Gandhi, Leela. Affective Communities: Anticolonial Thought, Fin-de-si cle Radicalism, and the Politics of Friendship. Durham: Duke University Press, 2006.
Gandhi, M. K. Hind Swaraj and Other Writings. Edited by Anthony J. Parel. Cambridge Texts in Modern Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Gaonkar, Dilip Parameshwar, ed. Alternative Modernities. Durham: Duke University Press, 2001.
Garrett, Edmund. Isis Very Much Unveiled: The Story of the Great Mahatma Hoax. 3rd ed. London: Westminster Gazette Office, 1894.
Gauchet, Marcel. The Disenchantment of the World. Translated by Oscar Burge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999.
Gilmartin, David. Election Law and the People in Colonial and Postcolonial India. In
From the Colonial to the Postcolonial: India and Pakistan in Transition, ed. Dipesh Chakrabarty, Rochona Majumdar, and Andrew Sartori, 55-84. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Glasenapp, H. von. Die Lehre Vallabhacaryas . Zeitschrift f r Indologie und Iranistik 9 (1933-34): 268-330.
--- . Doctrines of Vallabhacarya. Translated by I. S. Amin. Kapadwanj: Shri Shuddhatwaita Samsada, 1959.
Gold, Daniel. Organized Hinduisms: From Vedic Truth to Hindu Nation. In Fundamentalisms Observed, eds. Martin Marty and J. Scott Appleby, 531-93. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.
Goldie, Mark. Charles Blount's intention in writing King William and Queen Mary conquerors (1693). N&Q 223 (1978): 527 32.
---. Ideology. In Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, eds. Terence Ball, James Farr, and Russell L. Hanson, 266-291 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
Godwin, Joscelyn. The Theosophical Enlightenment. Albany: State Unversity of New York Press, 1994).
Grant, Charles. Observations on the State of Society among the Asiatic Subjects of Great Britain, 1792. House of Commons Parliamentary Papers Online.
http://gateway.proquest.com/openurl?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&res_dat=xri:hcppus&rft_dat=xri:hcpp:fulltext:1812-003343
Gribble, J. D. B. A Report of an Examination into the Blavatsky Correspondence, Published in the Christian College Magazine. Madras: Higginbotham and Co, 1884.
Growse, F. S. Mathura: A District Memoir. Allahabad: N. W. Provinces and Oudh Government Press, 1883.
Guha, Ranajit. The Prose of Counter-Insurgency. In Selected Subaltern Studies, ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, 45-88 (New York: Oxford Unviersity Press, 1988).
Gurney, Edmund, Frederic W. H. Myers, and Frank Podmore. Phantasms of the Living. Gainesville, FL: Scholars Fascimiles and Reprints, 1970 [1886].
Haberman, David L. On Trial: The Love of the Sixteen Thousand Gopees. History of Religions 33:1 (1993): 44-70.
--- . Journey Through the Twelve Forests: An encounter with Krishna. New York: Oxford, 1994.
Habermas, J rgen. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere. Translated by Thomas Burger and Frederick Lawrence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989.
Harrison, Peter. Religion and the Religions in the English Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Hart, William D. Edward Said and the Religious Effects of Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Hawley, John Stratton. The Memory of Love: Surdas Sings to Krishna. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Haynes, Douglas. Rhetoric and Ritual in Colonial India: The Shaping of a Public Culture in Surat City, 1852-1928. Berkeley: University of California, 1991.
Herbert of Cherbury, Lord Edward, De veritate, prout distinguitur a revelatione, a verisimili, a possibili, et a falso. Translated Meyrick H. Carr . Bristol: J. W. Arrowsmith, 1937 [1645].
--- . The antient religion of the gentiles, and causes of their errors consider d. London: William Taylor, 1711.
Heyd, Michael. Be Sober and Reasonable : The Critique of Enthusiasm in the Seventeenth and Early Eighteenth Centuries. Leiden: Brill, 1995.
High Court at Bombay, 1862-1962. Bombay: Government Central Press, 1962.
Hitchens, Christopher. God is not Great The Case Against Religion. London: Atlantic Books, 2007.
Hodgson, Richard. First Report of the Committee of the Society for Psychical Research, Appointed to Investigate the Evidence for Marvellous Phenomena Offered by Certain Members of the Theosophical Society. London: National Press Agency, 1884.
Hole, Charles. The Early History of the Church Missionary Society for Africa and the East. London: Church Missionary Society, 1896.
Holt, Francis Ludlow. The Law of Libel, in which is Contained a General History of this Law in the Ancient Codes and of its Introduction and Successive Alterations in the Law of England, Comprehending a Digest of All the Leading Cases upon Libels, from the Earliest to the Present Time. New York: Stephen Gould, 1818 [London, 1812].
Howitt, Margaret, ed. Mary Howitt: An Autobiography. 2 vols. London: W. Isbister, 1889.
Howitt, William. The Popular History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations. London and New York: Effingham Wilson, 1833.
--- . George Fox and his First Disciples; or, the Society of Friends as It Was, and as It Is. Philadelphia: Merrihew and Gunn, 1834.
--- . Colonization and Christianity: A Popular History of the Treatment of the Natives by the Europeans in All their Colonies. London: Longman, 1838.
Israel, Jonathan I. Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity, 1650-1750. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Jacob, Margaret C. The Radical Enlightenment: Pantheists, Freemasons, and Republicans. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1981.
Jaffrelot, Christophe. The Hindu Nationalist Movement in India. New York: Columbia University Press, 1996 [1993].
--- , ed. Hindu Nationalism: A Reader. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007.
Jakobsen, Janet R. and Ann Pellegrini, eds. Secularisms. Social Text Books. Durham: Duke University Press, 2008.
Jastrow, Morris. The Study of Religion. London: Charles Scribner, 1901.
Jennings, Hargrave. Review of The Occult World by A. P. Sinnett. Bombay: Gazette Steam Press, 1882.
Jinarajadas, C. The Story of the Mahatma Letters. 2nd ed. Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2000 [1946].
Jones, Kenneth W. Arya Dharm: Hindu Consciousness in 19th-Century Punjab. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976.
--- . Socio-religious Reform Movements in British India. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.
--- , ed. Religious Controversy in British India: Dialogues in South Asian Languages. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992.
Jones, William. Letters of William Jones. Edited by Garland Cannon. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970.
Jordans, J. T. H. Day"nanda Sarasvat(: His Life and Ideas. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1978.
Kaur, Raminder. Performative Politics and the Cultures of Hinduism: Public Uses of Religion in Western India. London: Anthem Press, 2005.
Khanna, Ranjana. Dark Continents: Psychoanalysis and Colonialism. Durham: Duke University Press, 2003.
King, Richard. Orientalism and Religion: Postcolonial Theory, India, and the Mystic East . London: Routledge, 1999.
Kippenberg, Hans. Discovering Religious History in the Modern Age. Translated by Barbara Harshav. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002.
L!l.a#kar, Narmad!.a#kar. M"r( Hak(kat. Edited by Ramesh M. Shukla. Amd!v!d: Par.va Publications, 2003.
Latham, Sean. The Art of Scandal: Modernism, Libel Law, and the Roman Clef. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Lease, Gary. Ideology. In Guide to the Study of Religion, ed. Willi Braun and Russell McCutcheon, 438-450. London: Cassell, 2000.
Leask, Nigel. Mythology. In An Oxford Companion to the Romantic Age: British Culture 17761832, ed. Iain McCalman, John Mee, Gillian Russell, Clara Tuite, Kate Fullagar, and Patsy Harvey, 338-344. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
Lee, Amice. Laurels and Rosemary: The Life of William and Mary Howitt. London: Oxford University Press, 1955.
Lillie, Arthur. Koot Hoomi Unveiled; or Tibetan Buddhists versus the Buddhists of Tibet. London: Psychological Press Association, c.1884.
Llewellyn, J. E. The Arya Samaj as a Fundamentalist Movement. New Delhi: Manohar, 1993.
Lopez, Donald S. Belief. In Critical Terms for Religious Studies, ed. Mark C. Taylor, 21-35. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998.
Lucian. The Religious Imposter, or, The Life of Alexander, a Sham Prophet, Doctor, and Fortune Teller. Translated by Sebastian Smith. Amsterdam?: n. p., c.1700.
L tt, J rgen. Max Weber and the Vallabhacharis. International Sociology 2.3 (September 1987): 277-287.
--- . From Krishnalila to Ramarajya: A Court Case and Its Consequences for the
Reformulation of Hinduism. In Representing Hinduism, eds. Vasudha Dalmia and Heinrich von Stietencron, 142-153. New Delhi: Sage Publications, 1995.
Madan, T. N. Secularism in Its Place, The Journal of Asian Studies 46.4 (1987): 748-49.
Mah"r"j L"(bal Kes tath" en( s"the sambandh rakhnar Bh"ti" Kansp(resi Kes (Mumbai: Daftar %.k!r! Ch!pkh!na, 1862),
Majeed, Javed. Ungoverned Imaginings: James Mill s History of British India and Orientalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.
Malabari, Behramji M. Gujarat and the Gujaratis. Delhi: Mittal Publications, 1983 [1889].
Anshu Malhotra, The Moral Woman and the Urban Punjabi Society of the Late Nineteenth Century. Social Scientist 20.5/6 (May-June 1992): 34-63.
--- . Every Woman is a Mother in Embryo: Lala Lajpat Rai and Indian Womanhood. Social Scientist, 22.1/2 (January-February 1994): 40-63.
Mani, Lata. Contentious Traditions: The Debate on Sati in Colonial India. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.
Mannheim, Karl. Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company 1936.
Manuel, Frank. The Eighteenth Century Confronts the Gods. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1959.
Marfatia, Mrudula. The Philosophy of Vallabhacarya. Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1967.
Marshall, P. J. The British Discovery of Hinduism in the Eighteenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970.
Martin, David. On Secularization: Towards a Revised General Theory. London: Ashgate, 2005.
Marx, Karl. Critique of Hegel s Philosophy of Right. In The Marx-Engels Reader, ed. Robert C. Tucker, 16-25. New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1972.
Massumi, Brian. A User s Guide to Capitalism and Schizophrenia: Deviations from Deleuze and Guattari. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Masuzawa, Tomoko. In Search of Dreamtime: The Quest for the Origin of Religion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.
--- . The Invention of World Religions, or, How European Universalism was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Maurice, Thomas. Indian Antiquities: or dissertations relative to the ancient geographical divisions, the pure system of primeval theology, the grand code of civil laws, the original form of government, and the various and profound literature of Hindostan. 7 vols. London: W. Richardson, 1793-1806.
--- . Brahminical Fraud Detected; or the Attempts of the Sacerdotal Tribe of India to Invest their Fabulous Deities and Heroes with the Honours and Attributes of the Christian Messiah, Examined, Exposed, and Defeated. London: W. Bulmer, 1812.
Metcalf, Barbara Daly. Perfecting Women: Maulana Asraf Ali Thanawi s Bihishti Zewar: A Partial Translation with Commentary. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990.
--- . Imagining Community: Polemical Debates in Colonial India. In Religious Controversy in British India: Dialogues in South Asian Languages, ed. Kenneth W. Jones, 229240. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992.
Mahatma Letters to A. P. Sinnett. Edited by A. T. Barker and Vincente Hao Chin, Jr. Adyar:
Theosophical Publishing House, 1998.
Mavalankar, Damodar. Damodar: The Writings of a Hindu Chela. Edited by Sven Eek. Point Loma, CA: Theosophical University Press, 1940.
Masselos, James C. The Khojas of Bombay: The Defining if Formal Membership Criteria During the Nineteenth Century. In Caste and Social Stratification among Muslims, ed. Imtiaz Ahmad, 1-20. Delhi: Manohar, 1973.
Maza, Sarah. Private Lives and Public Affairs: The Causes C l bres of Prerevolutionary France. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993.
McCutcheon, Russell. Manufacturing Religion: The Discourse on Sui Generis Religion and the Politics of Nostalgia. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.
McGarry, Molly. Ghosts of Futures Past: Spiritualism and the Cultural Politics of Nineteenth Century America. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008.
Mill, James. The History of British India. 4th ed. Edited by Horace Hayman Wilson. 6 vols. London: James Madden and Company, 1840.
Mill, John Stuart. Considerations on Representative Government. 2nd ed. London: Parker, Son, and Bourn, 1861.
Mills, Kenneth. Idolatry and its Enemies: Colonial Andean Religion and Extirpation, 1640-1750. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997.
Milton, John. Paradise Lost. Edited by Scott Elledge. New York: W.W. Norton, 1992.
Monier-Williams, Monier. Hinduism. Delhi: Rare Books, 1971 [1878?].
--- . Religious Thought and Life in India: An Account of the Religions of the Indian Peoples, Based on a Life s Study of their Literature and on Personal Investigations in their own Country. London: John Murray, 1883.
Mookerjee, Amalendu Prasad. Social and Political Ideas of Bipin Chandra Pal. Calcutta: Minerva Associates Publications, 1974.
Morgan, H. R. Reply to a Report of an Examination into the Blavatsky Correspondence by J.D.B. Gribble. 2nd ed. Ootacamud: Observer Press, 1884.
Morris, Henry. The Life of Charles Grant. London: J. Murray, 1904.
Motiwala, B. N. Karsondas Mulji: A Biographical Study. Bombay: Karsondas Mulji Centenary Celebration Committee, 1935.
Moulton, Edward C. The Beginnings of the Theosophical Movement in India, 18791885: Conversion and Non-Conversion Experiences. In Religious Conversion Movements in South Asia: Continuities and Change, 1800-1900, ed. Geoffrey A. Oddie, 109-172. Richmond, Surrey: Curzon Press, 1997.
Mufti, Aamir. Critical Secularism: A Reintroduction for Perilous Times. boundary 2 31:2 (2004): 1-9.
--- . Enlightenment in the Colony: The Jewish Question and the Crisis of Postcolonial Culture. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007.
Mukherjee, S. N. Sir William Jones: A Study in Eighteenth-Century British Attitudes to India. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968.
Mulji, Karsandas. Sansaarsukh: Domestic Happiness. Mumbai: Rising Star Printing Press, 1887 [1860].
--- . History of the Sect of Maharajas, or Vallabhac"ryas in Western India. London: Tr bner & Co, 1865.
--- . Nibandhamala: Essays on Social Subjects by Karsandas Mulji. Bombay: Union Press, 1870.
Nandy, Ashis. The Intimate Enemy: Loss and Recovery of Self under Colonialism. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983.
--- . An anti-secularist manifesto. Seminar 314 (1985): 14-24.
Narayan, Kirin. Storytellers, Saints, and Scoundrels: Folk Narrative in Hindu Religious Teaching. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1989.
A Native of Bombay, Now Resident in London. A Voice from India, Being an Appeal to the
British Legislature by Khojahs of Bombay, against the Usurped and Oppressive Domination of Hussain Hussanee, Commonly Called and Known as Aga Khan . London: Waterlow and Sons, 1864.
Needham, Anuradha Dingwaney and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan, eds. The Crisis of Secularism in India. Durham: Duke University Press, 2007.
Oddie, Geoffrey. Orientalism and British Protestant Missionary Constructions of India in the Nineteenth Century. South Asia 17.2 (1994): 27-42.
--- . Imagined Hinduism: British Protestant missionary constructions of Hinduism, 1793-1900.
New Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006.
Odgers, William Blake. A Digest of the Law of Libel and Slander. London: Stevens and Sons, 1881.
Olcott, Henry Steel. Inaugural Address of the President-Founder of the Theosophical Society, Delivered at Mott Memorial Hall, New York City, at the First Regular Meeting of the Society, Nov. 17, 1875. Adyar Pamphlet Series, No. 5. Benares and London: Theosophical Publishing Society, n.d.
--- . An Address by Col. Henry S. Olcott, President of the Theosophical Society, to the
Arya Samaj of Meerut, Delivered May 5th 1879, on the Occasion of a Public Welcome to a Committee of the Theosophical Society, by the Revered Swamee Daya Nand Saraswati, and the Meerut Samaj. Roorkee, India: Thomason Civil Engineering College Press, 1879.
--- . Theosophy: Its Friends and Enemies, Address delivered at Framji Cowasji Institute, Bombay, February 27, 1881. Bombay: Industrial Press, 1881.
--- . Jaratho#t( dharmn( m$l matlab vi#e bh".a/. Mumbai: Mumbai Sam!c!r, 1882.
--- . Old Diary Leaves: The History of the Theosophical Society. 6 vols. Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2002.
Oppenheim, Janet. The Other World: Spiritualism and Psychical Research In England, 18501914. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
Orme, Robert. Historical Fragments of the Mogul Empire. London: F. Windgrave, 1782.
Osho. Priests and Politicians: The Mafia of the Soul. Delhi: Full Circle, 1999 [1987].
Owen, Alex. The Darkened Room: Women, Power and Spiritualism in Late Nineteenth Century England. London: Virago, 1989.
--- . The Place of Enchantment: British Occultism and the Culture of the Modern. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.
Pailin, David A. Attitudes to Other Religions: Comparative Religion in Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century Britain. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1984.
Parekh, Manilal C. Shri Vallabhac"rya. Life, Teachings and Movement (A Religion of Grace). Rajkot: Shri Bhagavata Dharma Mission, 1969.
Pecora, Vincent. Secularization and Cultural Criticism: Religion, Nation, and Modernity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006.
Perry, Erskine. Cases Illustrative of Oriental Life and the Application of English Law to India, Decided in H. M. Supreme Court at Bombay. London: S. Sweet, 1853.
Pinney, Christopher. The Coming of Photography in India. London: British Library, 2008.
Pocock, J. G. A. Post-Puritan England and the Problem of the Enlightenment. In Culture and Politics from Puritanism to the Enlightenment, ed. Perez Zagorin. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1980.
Popkin, Richard. The History of Skepticism from Savanarola to Bayle. Revised edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.
Porter, Andrew. Religion Versus Empire? British Protestant Missionaries and Overseas Expansion, 1700-1914. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2004.
Potter Karl, ed. Advaita Ved"nta up to Samkara and his Pupils, vol. 3 of Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies. Delhi: M. Banarsidass,1981.
Powell, Avril. Muslims and Missionaries in Pre-Mutiny India. Richmond, Surrey: Curzon Press, 1993.
Preus, J. Samuel. Explaining Religion: Criticism and Theory from Bodin to Freud. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1987.
Prakash, Gyan. Another Reason: Science and the Imagination of Modern India. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999.
--- . The Impossibility of Subaltern History. Nepantla: Views from the South 1.2 (2000): 287-294.
Prasad, Leela. Poetics of Conduct: Oral Narrative and Moral Being in a South Indian Town. New York: Columbia University Press, 2007.
Prothero, Stephen R. The White Buddhist: The Asian Odyssey of Henry Steel Olcott. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996.
Purohit, Teena. Formations and Genealogies of Ismaili Sectarianism in Nineteenth Century India. Ph.D. diss., Columbia University, 2007.
Ranchhoddas, Ratanlal and Dhirajlal Keshavlal Thakore. The English and Indian Law of Torts. 19th ed. Bombay: Bombay Law Reporter Private Ltd, 1965 [1897].
Ransom, Josephine. A Short History of the Theosophical Society. Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 1938.
Ramaswamy, Sumathi. The Lost Land of Lemuria: Fabulous Geographies, Catastrophic Histories. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2004).
Redington, James D. Vallabhacarya on the Love-Games of Radha and Krsna. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1983.
Redwood, J. A. Charles Blount (1654 93), Deism, and English free thought. Journal of the History of Ideas 35 (1974): 490 98.
Report of the Committee Appointed to Investigate Phenomena Connected with the
Theosophical Society. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research 3 (1885): 201-400.
Report of the Maharaj Libel Case and of the Bhattia Conspiracy Case, Connected With It. Jadunathjee Birzrattanjee Maharaj, vs. Karsandass Mooljee Editor and Proprietor, and Nanabhai Rastamji Ranina, Printer, Satya Prakash . Bombay: Bombay Gazette Press, 1862.
Richman, Paula ed. Questioning Ramayanas: A South Asian Tradition. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001.
Risseuw, Carla. Thinking culture through counter-culture: the case of theosophists in India and Ceylon and their ideas on race and hierarchy (1875-1947). In Gurus and their followers, ed. Antony Copley. New York: Oxford 2000.
Roberts, Tylor. Rhetorics of Ideology and Criticism in the Study of Religion. Journal of Religion 85.3 (2005): 367-389.
Robinson, E. J. Tales and Poems of South India. London: T. Woolmer, 1885.
Robinson, Francis. Technology and the Impact of Print. Modern Asian Studies 27 (1993): 229251.
Rupram, Mahipatram. Uttam kapo): karsand"s mu)j(nu* caritra. Amd!v!d: Ranchodl!l Gangar!m, 1877.
Said, Edward. Orientalism. New York: Vintage Books, 1978.
--- . The World, the Text, and the Critic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983.
--- . Culture and Imperialism. New York: Knopf, 1993.
Sangari, Kumkum. The Politics of the Possible. Cultural Critique 7 (Autumn 1987): 157186.
Sangari, Kumkum and Sudesh Vaid, eds. Recasting Women: Essays in Indian Colonial History. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1990.
Sarda, Har Bilas. Life of Day"nand Saraswati, World Teacher. Ajmer: Vedic Yantralaya, 1946.
Sarkar, Tanika. Hindu Wife, Hindu Nation: Community, Religion, and Cultural Nationalism. New Delhi: Permanent Black, 2001.
Schmidt, Leigh Eric. From Demon Possession to Magic Show: Ventriloquism, Religion, and the Enlightenment. Church History 67.2 (1998): 274-304.
--- . Hearing Things: Religion, Illusion, and the American Enlightenment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.
Schwab, Raymond. The Oriental Renaissance: Europe s Rediscovery of India and the East, 16801880. New York: Columbia University Press, 1984.
Sears, Laurie J. Intellectuals, theosophy, and failed narratives of the nation in late colonial Java. In A Companion to Postcolonial Studies, ed. Henry Schwartz and Sangeeta Ray, 333-359. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2000.
Sen, Amartya. The Argumentative Indian: Writings on Indian History, Culture, and Identity. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2005.
Sharpe, Eric. Comparative Religion: A History, 2nd ed. LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1986 [1975].
Shodhan, Amrita. Women in the Maharaja Libel Case: A Re-examination. Indian Journal of Gender Studies 4:2 (1997). 123-139.
--- . A Question of Community: Religious Groups and Colonial Law. Calcutta: Samya, 2001.
Singh, Bawa Chhaju. Life and Teachings of Swami Day"nand Saraswati. New Delhi: Jan Gyan Prakashan, 1971 [1903].
Sinnett, A. P. The Occult World, 9th ed. London: Theosophical Publishing House, 1984 [1881].
--- . Incidents in the Life of Madame Blavatsky, Compiled from Information Supplied by her Relatives and Friends. London: Theosophical Publishing Society, 1913 [1886].
Sontheimer, G nther-Dietz and Hermann Kulke, eds. Hinduism Reconsidered. New Delhi: Manohar Publications, 1989.
Smith, Donald Eugene. India as a Secular State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963.
Smith, George. The Life of Alexander Duff. New York: American Tract Society, 1879.
Smith, Jonathan Z. Imagining Religion: From Babylon to Jonestown. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.
Smith, Wilfred Cantwell. The Meaning and End of Religion: A New Approach to the Religious Traditions of Mankind. New York: Macmillan, 1963.
Statham, John. Indian Recollections. London: Samuel Bagster, 1832.
Stock, Eugene. A History of the Church Missionary Society. 3 vols. London: Church Missionary Society, 1899.
Stokes, Eric. English Utilitarians and India. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959.
Storr, Anthony. Feet of Clay: Saints, Sinners, and Madmen: A Study of Gurus. New York: Free Press, 1996.
Styers, Randall. Making Magic: Religion, Magic, and Science in the Modern World. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.
Taussig, Michael. Shamanism, Colonialism, and the Wild Man: A Study in Terror and Healing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987.
Taylor, Charles. A Secular Age. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 2007.
Taylor, Mark C. After God. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007.
Thakkar, Usha. Puppets on the Periphery: Women and Social Reform in 19th Century Gujarati Society. Economic and Political Weekly 32 (1997): 46-52.
Thapar, Romila. The Theory of Aryan Race and India: History and Politics. Social Scientist, 24.1/3 (November 1996): 3-29.
Thompson, Stith and Warren E. Roberts. Types of Indic Oral Tales: India, Pakistan, and Ceylon. Helsinki: Suomalainen Tiedeakatemia, 1960.
Thoothi, N. A. The Vai%!avas of Gujarat. Calcutta: Longmans, Green & Co., 1935.
Thursby, Gene R. Hindu-Muslim Relations in British India. Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1975.
Trait des Trois Imposteurs. Amsterdam?: n. p., 1775?
Toland, John. Pantheisticon, Or the Form of Celebrating the Socratic Society. London: Sam Paterson, 1751.
Tollenaere, Herman A. O. de. The Politics of Divine Wisdom: Theosophy and labour, national, and women s movements in Indonesia and South Asia, 1875-1947. Leiden: Uitgeverij Katholieke Universiteit Nijmegan, 1996.
Tweed, Thomas A. Crossing and Dwelling: A Theory of Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006.
Upreti, Pandit Ganga Datt Proverbs and Folklore of Kumaun and Garhwal. Lodiana: Lodiana Mission Press, 1894.
Vaidya, Chimanlal. Shri Vallabhacharya and His Teachings. Translated by Bhailalbhai N. Shastri. Baroda: Shri Vallabha Publications, 1984.
Vaidya, Vijayarai Kalyanrai. Gujar"t( Sahity" R$parekh". Amd!v!d: Ravani Prak!.an G/h, 1973.
Van der Veer, Peter. Imperial Encounters: Religion and Modernity in India and Britain. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Viswanathan, Gauri. Masks of Conquest: Literary Study and British Rule in India. New York: Columbia University Press, 1989
--- . Outside the Fold: Conversion, Modernity, and Belief. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998.
--- . The Ordinary Business of Occultism, Criticial Inquiry 27 (Autumn 2000): 1-20.
--- . Secularism in the Framework of Heterodoxy, PMLA 123.2 (2008): 466-476.
Vries, Hent de. Philosophy and the Turn to Religion. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999.
--- . In Media Res: Global Religion, Public Spheres, and the Task of Contemporary Comparative Religious Studies, in Religion and Media, ed. Hent de Vries and Samuel Weber, 3-42. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001.
--- , ed. Religion: Beyond a Concept. New York: Fordham University Press, 2008.
Wadia, K. J. B. Fifty Years of Theosophy in Bombay. Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 1931.
Walber, Karl Josef. Charles Blount (1654-1693), Fr haufkl rer: Leben und Werk. Frankfurt um Main: P. Laing, 1988.
Ward, William. A View of the History, Literature, and Mythology of the Hindoos. 2nd ed. Serampore: Mission Press 1818.
Warner, Michael. The Letters of the Republic: Publication and the Public Sphere in EighteenthCentury America. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.
--- . Publics and Counterpublics. New York: Zone Books, 2002.
Washington, Peter. Madame Blavatsky s Baboon: Theosophy and the Emergence of the Western Guru. London: Secker and Warburg, 1993.
Who Speaks for Hinduism? Spec. issue of Journal of the American Academy of Religion 68.4 (2000).
Weber, Max. Science as Vocation. In From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills, 129-158. New York: Oxford University Press, 1946.
Wilson, Horace Hayman. Sketch of the Religious Sects of the Hindus. Calcutta: Bishop s College Press, 1846.
Wolsey, Charles. The unreasonableness of atheism made manifest. 3rd ed. London: Nathaniel Ponder, 1675.
Woodring, Carl Ray. Victorian Samplers: William and Mary Howitt. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press, 1952.
Yadun!th Mah!r!j Suratv!,!. Svadharm vardhak ane sa*#ay chedek. 17 vols. Amd!v!d: Gujarat Printing Press, 1911.
Zagorin, Perez. Ways of Lying: Dissimulation, Persecution, and Conformity in Early Modern Europe Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.
Zavos, John. The Arya Samaj and the Antecedents of Hindu Nationalism. International Journal of Hindu Studies 3:1 (April 1999): 57-81.
Zirkoff, Boris de. How Isis Unveiled was Written. In Isis Unveiled, Helena Petrovna Blavatsky, ed. Boris de Zirkoff. 2 vols. Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2006.
&i ek, Slavoj. How the Non-Duped Err. Qui Parle 4.1 (1990): 1-20.
--- , ed. Mapping Ideology. London: Verso, 1994.
Joshua Barton Scott was born in 1978 and grew up in Kentucky. He graduated from Lexington s Henry Clay High School in 1997. Bart attended Swarthmore College and graduated with honors in 2001, with a double major in Religion and English Literature.
He began his doctoral work at Duke University s Graduate Program in Religion in 2003. His graduate studies were funded by a James B. Duke Fellowship, as well as fellowships from the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation and the North Carolina Center for South Asian Studies. His dissertation research was made possible by grants from the American
Institute for Indian Studies, the American Institute for Pakistan Studies, and Duke
University. He currently resides in Evanston, Illinois.
[1] Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel s Philosophy of Right, in The Marx-Engels Reader, ed. Robert C. Tucker (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1972), 12.
[2] Hindoo Delusions, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1820), 121.
[3] Karsandas Mulji s Travels, Bombay Saturday Review, August 4, 1866
[4] A note about orthography: throughout the dissertation, I use the archaic spelling brahmin to signal period rhetoric about Indian religions, both inside and outside marked quotations. When referring to the var!a in a more neutral sense, I use the preferred spelling, brahman. Capitalization should occur only within quotations. Apologies for any confusion caused by this necessary inconsistency.
[5] See Michel Foucault, Nietzsche, Genealogy, History, in Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews, ed. Donald F. Bouchard, trans. Bouchard and Sherry Simon (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977), 139-164. According to Foucault, genealogy disturbs what was previously considered immobile; it fragments what was thought unified; it shows the heterogeneity of what was imagined consistent with itself (147).
[6] Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions, 2.
[7] Asad, Genealogies of Religion., 28.
[8] Hent de Vries, ed., Religion: Beyond a Concept (New York: Fordham University Press, 2008).
[9] See Asad, Masuzawa, Styers, Chidester, King, and Balagangadhara.
[10] See Ashis Nandy, The Intimate Enemy: Loss and Recovery of Self under Colonialism (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983).
[11] Masuzawa, Invention of World Religions, 19
[12] Janet R. Jakobsen and Ann Pellegrini, Introduction: Times Like These, in Secularisms, ed. Janet R.
Jakobsen and Ann Pellegrini, Social Text Books (Durham: Duke University Press, 2008), 1.
[13] The revisionist literature on secularism is far larger than can be covered here. For a representatively interdisciplinary sampling see the following: Jos Casanova, Public Religions in the Modern World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); Rajeev Bhargava, ed., Secularism and its Critics (Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 1998); William E. Connolly, Why I am not a Secularist (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
[14] ); David Martin, On Secularization: Towards a Revised General Theory (London: Ashgate, 2005); and Vincent Pecora, Secularization and Cultural Criticism: Religion, Nation, and Modernity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006).
[15] Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 2007); Marcel Gauchet, The Disenchantment of the World, trans. Oscar Burge (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999).
[16] Talal Asad, Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003).
[17] Ashis Nandy, An anti-secularist manifesto, Seminar 314 (1985): 14-24; T. N. Madan, Secularism in Its Place, The Journal of Asian Studies 46.4 (1987): 748-49. One might compare the subaltern studies collective s frequent association of secularism with the urban elite and religion with the peasantry. See Ranajit Guha, The Prose of Counter-Insurgency, in Selected Subaltern Studies, ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (New York: Oxford Unviersity Press, 1988), 81; Dipesh Chakrabarty, The Death of History?: Historical Consciousness and the Culture of Late Capitalism, Public Culture 4.2 (1992): 52-53.
[18] See, for instance, the essays in Anuradha Dingwaney Needham and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan, eds., The Crisis of Secularism in India (Durham: Duke University Press, 2007). For an important earlier study of Indian state secularism, see Donald Eugene Smith, India as a Secular State (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963).
[19] Amartya Sen, The Argumentative Indian: Writings on Indian History, Culture, and Identity (New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2005).
[20] Edward Said, Culture and Imperialism (New York: Knopf, 1993), 42, 318.
[21] Peter van der Veer, Imperial Encounters: Religion and Modernity in India and Britain (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 7-8.
[22] Gauri Viswanathan, Masks of Conquest: Literary Study and British Rule in India (New York: Columbia University Press, 1989).
[23] Gauri Viswanathan, Outside the Fold: Conversion, Modernity, and Belief (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998); Aamir R. Mufti, Enlightenment in the Colony: The Jewish Question and the Crisis of Postcolonial Culture (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007).
[24] For example, Wilfred Cantwell Smith has argued that the rudiments of the concept religion emerged much earlier than is often supposed and in a much more diffuse geographical zone. In Smith s view, Islam not only anticipated the reification of belief that would define modern Western cultures; these two developments should be understood as part of the same historical process. Islam thus does far more than provide a special case, as Smith puts it, for those who would challenge the concept religion s universal applicability. It redefines the entire field of research. In order to track the full genealogy of religion, one would need to develop a contrapuntal method that follows it across such cultural divides. Smith, The Meaning and End of Religion. See also Talal Asad. "Reading a Modern Classic: W. C. Smith's The Meaning and End of Religion," History of Religions 40.3 (2001): 205-22.
[25] Asad, Formations of the Secular, 16.
[26] This list is borrowed from Van der Veer, Imperial Encounters, 14. The critical interrogation of
tolerance has proved particularly productive. See, for instance, Wendy Brown, Regulating Aversion:
[27] Smith, The Meaning and End of Religion, 43. Smith s account of the emergence of religion is in some ways remarkably resonant with Foucault, who insisted in his essay on the genealogical method that new discursive entities emerge from the interstitial spaces of struggle, such that neither competing party can claim authorship. See Nietzsche, Genealogy, History, 150.
[28] These are (a) religion as piety, (b) discrete religions (e.g. Christianity ) as the ideal object of theology, (c) discrete religions as the ideal object of the human sciences, and (d) religion as a generalized essence (which Smith dates to Friedrich Schleiermacher s 1799 ber die Religion). See Meaning and End of Religion.
[29] Brian Massumi, A User s Guide to Capitalism and Schizophrenia: Deviations from Deleuze and Guattari (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 80.
[30] Gauri Viswanathan, Secularism in the Framework of Heterodoxy, PMLA 123.2 (2008): 469, 476.
[31] For the munazara, see Avril Powell, Muslims and Missionaries in Pre-Mutiny India (Richmond, Surrey:
Curzon Press, 1993); for the sh"str"rth, see Catherine Adcock, Religious Freedom and Political Culture: The Arya Samaj in Colonial North India (Ph.D. diss., University of Chicago, 2007).
[32] J rgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, trans. Thomas Burger and Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989); Sandria Freitag, Collective Action and Community: Public Arenas in the Emergence of Communalism in North India (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1990); and Sandria Freitag, ed., Aspects of the Public in Colonial South Asia, spec. issue of South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 14.1 (1991). For other major inquiries into formations of the South Asian public sphere, see C. A. Bayly, Empire and Information: Intelligence Gathering and Social Communication in India, 1780-1870 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997); Sumanta Banerjee, The Parlour and the Streets: Elite and Popular Culture in Nineteenth Century Calcutta (Calcutta: Seagull Books, 1989); Douglas Haynes, Rhetoric and Ritual in Colonial India: The Shaping of a Public Culture in Surat City, 1852-1928 (Berkeley: University of California, 1991); Raminder Kaur, Performative Politics and the Cultures of Hinduism: Public Uses of Religion in Western India (London: Anthem Press, 2005).
[33] Lawrence A. Babb and Susan S. Wadley, eds., Media and the Transformation of Religion in South Asia (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1995), 21.
[34] For print capitalism, see Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism (London: Verso, 1991). For an argument about how religious movements like the Brahmo Samaj, Theosophical Society, and the Ramakrishna Mission proffered cosmopolitan syncretisms, see Srinivas Aravamudan, Guru English: South Asian Religion in a Cosmopolitan Language (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006).
[35] See, for instance, Francis Robinson, Technology and the Impact of Print, Modern Asian Studies 27 (1993): 229251.
[36] Barbara Daly Metcalf, Imagining Community: Polemical Debates in Colonial India, in Religious Controversy in British India: Dialogues in South Asian Languages, ed. Kenneth W. Jones (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), 232-233.
[37] This has been true for other historical contexts as well. For the argument that modes of political subjectivity fostered in private by eighteenth century literature were crucial to the revolutionary politics of 1789 and afterward, see Habermas, Structural Transformation, and Sarah Maza Private Lives and Public Affairs: The Causes C l bres of Prerevolutionary France (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993). For a reconsideration of how the private is implicated by the public, with primary reference to the United States, see Michael Warner, Publics and Counterpublics (New York: Zone Books, 2002).
[38] See Michael Warner, Letters of the Republic: Publication and the Public Sphere in Eighteenth Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990). This is discussed at greater length in Chapter Two.
[39] Partha Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993). British imperial ideologies also affected the shape of Indian cultural publics. Nicholas Dirks, for instance, has argued that caste served as the organizing concept for the imperial effort to invalidate colonial civil society as inherently, even atavistically, apolitical. See Castes of Mind:
Colonialism and the Making of Modern India (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001).
[40] Stree Bodh, the Gujarati periodical edited by Karsandas Mulji, is exemplary of this trend. Compare Barbara Daly Metcalf, Perfecting Women: Maulana Asraf Ali Thanawi s Bihishti Zewar: A Partial Translation with Commentary (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990).
[41] The most influential text in this regard is surely Amartya Sen, Argumentative Indian. In a very different vein, see the focused inquires into ethical argument in Leela Prasad, Poetics of Conduct: Oral Narrative and Moral Being in a South Indian Town (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007); and Paula Richman, ed., Questioning Ramayanas: A South Asian Tradition (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001).
[42] Captious and Sceptical Spirit of some of the Natives, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1826), 431-432.
[43] Report of the Maharaj Libel Case and of the Bhattia Conspiracy Case, Connected With It. Jadunathjee Birzrattanjee Maharaj, vs. Karsandass Mooljee Editor and Proprietor, and Nanabhai Rastamji Ranina, Printer, Satya Prakash (Bombay: Bombay Gazette Press, 1862), 170.
[44] Henry Steel Olcott, An Address by Col. Henry S. Olcott, President of the Theosophical Society, to the
Arya Samaj of Meerut, Delivered May 5th 1879, on the Occasion of a Public Welcome to a Committee of the Theosophical Society, by the Revered Swamee Daya Nand Saraswati, and the Meerut Samaj (Roorkee, India: Thomason Civil Engineering College Press, 1879), 2-4.
[45] Dipesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), 27-28.
[46] Ibid., 16.
[47] Cf. Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse? (London: Zed Books, 1986).
[48] Sen, The Argumentative Indian.
[49] Sumathi Ramaswamy, The Lost Land of Lemuria: Fabulous Geographies, Catastrophic Histories (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2004), 16.
[50] M. K. Gandhi, Hind Swaraj and Other Writings, ed. Anthony J. Parel, Cambridge Texts in Modern Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 43-44. This rhetorical strategy occurs elsewhere in the text. For instance: like the selfish and false religious teachers, who divide Hindu from Muslim, the English pretend to study the manners and customs of all peoples. God has given us a limited mental capacity, but they usurp the function of the Godhead and indulge in novel experiments. They write about their own researches in laudatory terms and hypnotize us into believing them. We, in our ignorance, then fall at their feet (56). In other words, when the English take on the universal perspective of social science, they pretend to be gods, and in this are no different than the many pretended godmen of India.
[51] Mark Goldie, Ideology, in Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, eds. Terence Ball, James Farr, and Russell L. Hanson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 279; cf. Richard Ashcraft,
Anticlericalism and authority in Lockean political thought, in The Margins of Orthodoxy: Heterodox Writing and Cultural Response, 1660-1750, ed. Roger D. Lund (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1995), 73-96.
[52] Trait des Trois Imposteurs (Amsterdam?: s.n., 1775?).
[53] Lucian, The Religious Imposter, or, The Life of Alexander, a Sham Prophet, Doctor, and Fortune Teller, trans.
Sebastian Smith (Amsterdam?: c1700), 11.
[54] Champion, Religion s Safe, 554.
[55] Donald S. Lopez, Belief, in Critical Terms for Religious Studies, ed. Mark C. Taylor (Chicago and London: University of Chicago, 1998) 21-35.
[56] Jacques Derrida, Faith and Knowledge, trans. Sam Weber, in Acts of Religion, ed. Gil Anijdar, (New York: Routledge, 2002), 80-82.
[57] Richard A. Davenport, Sketches of Imposture, Deception, and Credulity (London: Thomas Tegg and Sons, 1837), 1.
[58] Slavoj &i ek, How the Non-Duped Err, Qui Parle 4.1 (1990): 9.
[59] Slavoj &i ek, The Spectre of Ideology, in Slavoj &i ek, ed., Mapping Ideology (London: Verso, 1994): 133.
[60] Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company 1936), 54.
[61] Hent de Vries, Philosophy and the Turn to Religion (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999), 11.
[62] J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975).
[63] Jacques Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), 325326
[64] Compare David Chidester s suggestion that even religious fakes still do authentic religious work ; in Authentic Fakes: Religion and American Popular Culture (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005), vii.
[65] During, Modern Enchantments, 44-45.
[66] Practical Instructions for Students of Occultism: Forbidden Fruit, The Theosophist, September 1884, 291-292. This was published in the same month that the Madras Christian College Magazine published its notorious expos of Madame H. P. Blavatsky (see Chapter 5).
[67] Charles Wolsey, The unreasonableness of atheism made manifest, 3rd ed. (London: Nathaniel Ponder, 1675), 198.
[68] William Howitt, The Popular History of Priestcraft in All Ages and Nations (London and New York: Effingham Wilson, 1833), 14. Henceforth cited in text as PHP.
[69] Carl Ray Woodring, Victorian Samplers: William and Mary Howitt (Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press, 1952). The other major biography of the Howitts is Amice Lee, Laurels and Rosemary: The Life of William and Mary Howitt (London: Oxford University Press, 1955).
[70] Simon During, Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002).
[71] Margaret Howitt, ed., Mary Howitt: An Autobiography, vol. 1 (London: W. Isbister, 1889), 233-34.
[72] Ibid., 233
[73] Woodring, Victorian Samplers, 42-43. Howitt s article was later reprinted as George Fox and his First Disciples; or, the Society of Friends as It Was, and as It Is (Philadelphia: Merrihew and Gunn, 1834).
[74] Gauri Viswanathan, Outside the Fold: Conversion, Modernity, and Belief (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998), 4-5. Meanwhile, in India, Maucaulay s educational program, designed to produce people who were Indian in blood and colour, but English in taste, in opinions, in morals, and in intellect, sought in effect to produce non-Muslim Muslims and non-Hindu Hindus.
[75] Mary Howitt, letter of January 1834; in Margaret Howitt, ed., Autobiography, 237-39.
[76] Other references to Diana of the Ephesians occur on pages 124 and 196.
[77] See Frank Manuel, The Eighteenth Century Confronts the Gods (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
[78] ); Peter Harrison, Religion and the Religions in the English Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990); Justin Champion, The Pillars of Priestcraft Shaken: The Church of England and its
Enemies, 1660-1730 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992); Justin Champion, Religion s Safe, with Priestcraft is the War: Augustan Anticlericalism and the Legacy of the English Revolution, 1660-1720, The European Legacy 5.4 (2000): 547-561; and Leigh Eric Schmidt, Hearing Things: Religion, Illusion, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
[79] See Karl Josef Walber, Charles Blount (1654-1693), Fr haufkl rer: Leben und Werk (Frankfurt um Main: P. Laing, 1988); Mark Goldie, Charles Blount's intention in writing King William and Queen Mary conquerors (1693), N&Q 223 (1978): 527 32; J. A. Redwood, Charles Blount (1654 93), Deism, and English free thought, Journal of the History of Ideas 35 (1974): 490 98.
[80] This term has been used to denote the period s most ardently materialistic and atheistic thinkers, whose clandestine conversations about scandalous topics like Spinoza forged cosmopolitan connections across Europe. See Margaret C Jacob, The Radical Enlightenment: Pantheists, Freemasons, and Republicans (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1981); and Jonathan I. Israel, Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity, 1650-1750 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
[81] The text was first published in French in 1719, under the title L Esprit de M. Spinosa and subsequently entered multiple editions. For discussion of the authorship of the Trait , see Jacob, 55, as well as the essays collected in Sylvia Berti, Fran oise Charles-Daubert, and Richard H. Popkin, eds., Heterodoxy, Spinozism, and Free Thought in Early-Eighteenth-Century Europe: Studies on the Trait des Trois Imposteurs (Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996).
[82] The treatise of the three impostors and the problem of Enlightenment : a new translation of the Trait des trois imposteurs (1777 edition), trans. Abraham Anderson (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997), II.xi.28.
[83] Harrison, Religion and the Religions, 73.
[84] Charles Blount, Anima Mundi, or, An historical narration of the opinions of the ancients concerning man s soul after this life (London: Will Cademan, 1679), 2-5.
[85] Charles Blount, A Summary Account of the Deists Religion, in Oracles of Reason (London: 1693), 88-96.
[86] Harrison, Religion and the Religions, 73.
[87] John Eachard, Grounds and Occasions of the Contempt of the Clergy and Religion Enquired Into (London: W. Godbid, 1670). Not surprisingly, Eachard associates outright fraud with the Catholic Continent: it is there that Cheats, contriv d Tales, and feigned Miracles are used by priests to accrue Money in abundance (98).
[88] Jeremy Collier, A Short View of the Immorality and Profaneness of the English Stage, 2nd ed. (London: Kable, Sare, and Hindmarsh, 1698), 81. For discussion of Collier, see Justin Champion, Religion s Safe, 552-553; and Rose Anthony, The Jeremy Collier Stage Controversy, 1698-1726 (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1937).
[89] J. G. A. Pocock, Post-Puritan England and the Problem of the Enlightenment, in Culture and Politics from Puritanism to the Enlightenment, ed. Perez Zagorin (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1980), 106.
[90] Champion, Pillars of Priestcraft, 14.
[91] Bernard le Boivier de Fontenelle, Histoire des oracles, ed. Louis Maigron (Paris: E. Corn ly, 1908); Bernard le Boivier Fontenelle, The History Oracles, and the Cheats of Pagan Priests, trans. Aphra Behn (London: 1688).
[92] Manuel, Eighteenth Century, 49
[93] I borrow this distinction from Simon During, Modern Enchantments
[94] Michel de Certeau, The Possession at Loudun, trans. Michael B. Smith (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000), 144. For other discussions of how anxiety about religious enthusiasm, demonic possession, and magic contributed to the emergence of modern medical institutions, see Michael Heyd, Be Sober and Reasonable : The Critique of Enthusiasm in the Seventeenth and Early Eighteenth Centuries (Leiden: Brill, 1995); and Randall Styers, Making Magic: Religion, Magic, and Science in the Modern World (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004).
[95] Richard Popkin has suggested that Loudun s perfidious demons inspired Descartes s demon hypothesis, the evil genius that threatened to topple his meditations with a pervasive and insurmountable delusion. See The History of Skepticism from Savanarola to Bayle, rev. ed. (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), 149-150.
[96] For a highly suggestive discussion of demonic possession in seventeenth-century Peru, see Kenneth
Mills, Idolatry and its Enemies: Colonial Andean Religion and Extirpation, 1640-1750 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997); see also Fernando Cervantes, The Devil in the New World: The Impact of Diabolism in New Spain (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994).
[97] Quotations from John Milton, Paradise Lost, ed. Scott Elledge, 2nd ed. (New York: W.W. Norton, 1992), IV.121-122 and IX.644.
[98] Leigh Eric Schmidt, From Demon Possession to Magic Show: Ventriloquism, Religion, and the Enlightenment, Church History 67.2 (1998): 226.
[99] Ibid., 225
[100] In Hearing Things, Schmidt offers an especially rich account of how the period s entertainers and philosophers trained the ear to hear reasonably and remain immune to the lure of divine (and demonic) voices. He refigures imposture as a diffuse discipline, a discourse complicit with new regimes of capillary control over crowds and bodies, but a discipline also vulnerable to the enthusiastic eruptions of spirit that modern acoustics could never quite muffle.
[101] Quotations from Blount, 42-43. Compare Fontenelle: ). et pourquoy ils ne s avisoient jamais d aller anime une Stat e qui fust dans un Carrefour, expos de toutes parts aux yeux de tout le monde (Histoire, 115-116).
[102] Manuel, Eighteenth Century, 65-69
[103] John Toland, Pantheisticon, Or the Form of Celebrating the Socratic Society (London: Sam Paterson, 1751), iii.
[104] Harrison, Religion and the Religions, 85.
[105] Manuel, Eighteenth Century, 65. This mythology of intellectuals noble dissemblance in the face of ignorant authority may have proved especially appealing to early modern radical thinkers constrained by state censorship. See Perez Zagorin, Ways of Lying: Dissimulation, Persecution, and Conformity in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
[106] Harrison, Religion and the Religions, 73, 78.
[107] Manuel, Eighteenth Century, 15-19
[108] S.N. Balagangadhara The Heathen in His Blindness: Asia, the West, and the Dynamic of Religion (Leiden: Brill,
[109] ), 100
[110] Collier, Short View of the Immorality, 95
[111] Mary Howitt, letter of December 19, 1832; in Margaret Howitt, ed., Autobiography, 231.
[112] Nigel Leask, Mythology, in An Oxford Companion to the Romantic Age: British Culture 1776-1832, ed. Iain McCalman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 338-345. My account here draws heavily on Leask. See also Manuel, Eighteenth Century Confronts the Gods; P. J. Marshall, The British Discovery of Hinduism in the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970); Raymond Schwab, The Oriental Renaissance: Europe s Rediscovery of India and the East, 1680-1880 (New York, 1984); and David A. Pailin, Attitudes to Other Religions: Comparative Religion in Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century Britain (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1984).
[113] See Jacob Bryant, A New System; or, Analysis of Antient Mythology: wherein an attempt is made to divest tradition of fable, and to reduce the truth to its original purity, 6 vols. (London: J. Walker, 1807 [1774-76]).
[114] Thomas Maurice, Indian Antiquities: or dissertations relative to the ancient geographical divisions, the pure system of primeval theology, the grand code of civil laws, the original form of government, and the various and profound literature of Hindostan, 7 vols. (London: W. Richardson, 1793-1806). Also of interest is Maurice s Brahminical Fraud Detected; or the Attempts of the Sacerdotal Tribe of India to Invest their Fabulous Deities and
Heroes with the Honours and Attributes of the Christian Messiah, Examined, Exposed, and Defeated (London: W.
[115] William Howitt, Colonization and Christianity: A Popular History of the Treatment of the Natives by the Europeans in All their Colonies (London: Longman, 1838), i.
[116] Ibid., 507
[117] Woodring, Victorian Samplers, 52-53.
[118] Sven Lindqvist, The Skull Measurer s Mistake: And Other Portraits of Men and Women who Spoke Out against Racism, trans. Joan Tate (New York: New Press, 1997), 51-52.
[119] Thomas Maurice, Indian Antiquities, vol. 7 (London: John White, 1800), 801.
[120] William Ward, A View of the History, Literature, and Mythology of the Hindoos, 2nd ed. (Serampore: Mission Press 1818). The first quotation is taken from Geoffrey Oddie, Imagined Hinduism: British Protestant missionary constructions of Hinduism, 1793-1900 (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006), 165; the second quotation from Missionary Register (London: L. B. Seeley,1822), 175.
[121] Notices of Hindoo Superstition and Cupidity, Missionary Register (L. B. Seeley, 1832), 525.
[122] William Jones, Letters of William Jones, ed. Garland Cannon, vol. 2 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), 754; cited in Oddie, Imagined Hinduism, 106.
[123] John Statham, Indian Recollections (London: Samuel Bagster, 1832), 101.
[124] Duff presents Hinduism as a stupendous example of the systems of false religion that have been fabricated by the perverse ingenuity of fallen man. It is Christianity s counterfeit because it corrupted the primitive patriarchal Christianity of which Duff, presumably, is the heir. Duff s reliance on the narratives of religious origin developed during the English Enlightenment should be obvious (see Chapter 1). Alexander Duff, India and India Missions: Including Sketches of the Gigantic System of Hinduism, Both in Theory and Practice, 2nd ed. (Edinburgh: John Johnstone, 1840), 204.
[125] Several scholars have responded to what Jeffrey Cox has termed the Saidian presumption of imperial complicity. See Imperial Fault Lines: Christianity and Colonial Power in India, 1818-1914 (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000), 12. Robert Frykenberg is surely the leading scholar of Indian Christianity, and he quite rightly points out that, even during the nineteenth century Thomist Christians, Portuguese Catholics, and others continued to played significant roles, particularly in regions like Tamil Nadu and
Goa. See especially his monumental Christianity in India: From Beginnings to the Present (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2008). See also the essays in Robert Frykenberg and Alaine Low, eds., Christians and Missionaries in India: Cross-Cultural Communication since 1500, with special reference to caste, conversion, and colonialism (Grand Rapids, MI. : W.B. Eerdmans, 2003); Geoffrey Oddie, Orientalism and British Protestant Missionary Constructions of India in the Nineteenth Century, South Asia 17.2 (1994): 27-42; and Andrew Porter, Religion Versus Empire? British Protestant Missionaries and Overseas Expansion, 1700-1914 (Manchester and New York: Manchester University Press, 2004). Much of this research has emphasized the complex effects of Indians conversions to British Protestantism. In this regard, see also Gauri Viswanathan, Outside the Fold: Conversion, Modernity, Belief (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998). Additional accounts of missionary activity in the subcontinent include the following: George Smith, The Life of Alexander Duff (New York: American Tract Society, 1879); Henry Morris, The Life of Charles Grant (London: J. Murray, 1904); Ainslee Embree, Charles Grant and the British Rule in India (London: G. Allen, 1962); Antony Copley, Religions in conflict: ideology, cultural contact, and conversion in late-colonial India (Delhi and New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); and Lata Mani, Contentious Traditions: The Debate on Sati in Colonial India (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998).
[126] Duff, India and India Missions, 63
[127] Nicholas Dirks, Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of Modern India (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001).
[128] Nicholas Dirks, The Scandal of Empire: India and the Creation of Imperial Britain (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2006), 297.
[129] Missionary Register (London: L. B. Seeley, 1830), 456-57.
[130] Montesquieu and Adam Smith authored the main modern articulations of the notion of Oriental despotism, and their work was further developed by Hegel, Marx, and others. For an account of the
[131] James Mill, The History of British India, 6 vols., 4th ed., ed. Horace Hayman Wilson (London: James Madden and Company, 1840), 202-203.
[132] Ibid., 218-220
[133] Ibid., 187
[134] Eric Stokes, English Utilitarians and India (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959), 54.
[135] John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government, 2nd ed. (London: Parker, Son, and Bourn, 1861), 39.
[136] Duff, India and India Missions, 61-64.
[137] Michel Foucault, The Subject and Power, in Michel Foucault, Power, ed. James D. Faubion (New York: New Press, 2000), 326-348.
[138] See Oddie, Imagining Hinduism, 70.
[139] Charles Grant, Observations on the State of Society among the Asiatic Subjects of Great Britain, 1792, House of Commons Parliamentary Papers Online., 73. (Hereafter cited in text as OSS). http://gateway.proquest.com/openurl?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&res_dat=xri:hcppus&rft_dat=xri:hcpp:fulltext:1812-003343
[140] Michael Warner, The Letters of the Republic: Publication and the Public Sphere in Eighteenth-Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 5-7.
[141] Ibid., 8
[142] Ibid., 62
[143] See also Allan K. Davidson s study of Claudius Buchanan as a publicist: Evangelicals and Attitudes to India,
[144] -1813: Missionary publicity and Claudius Buchanan (Appleford, Abingdon, Berkshire: Sutton Courtenay Press, 1990). Davidson argues that the major difference between Buchanan and his predecessor Charles Grant was the latter s insistence on the importance of print publicity.
[145] Quoted in Oddie, Imagining Hinduism, 205. For additional discussion of the CMS, see Charles Hole, The
Early History of the Church Missionary Society for Africa and the East (London: CMS, 1896); and Eugene Stock, A History of the Church Missionary Society, 3 vols. (London: CMS, 1899). For additional discussion of missionary periodicals as a mechanism for publicity, see Davidson, Chapter 5, Missionary Publicity, 96-107.
[146] Oddie, Imagining Hinduism, 205-209.
[147] Missionary Register (London: L. B. Seeley, 1823), 402.
[148] In accounts of widow burning, the typical scene featured a maddened crowd led by a powerful priest who pushes the widow onto the pyre. Bowley s journal includes an episode in which the sati herself addresses the credulous multitude in order to assert her pending divinity. See the Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1829), 322. The procession of the Juggernaut (i.e. the Lord Jaggan!th, associated especially with his annual chariot procession in the Orissan coastal city of Puri) likewise featured crowds. In the words of one Lt. Col. Phipps of the 13th Bengal Native Infantry, the approach of the Juggernaut was generally proceeded by a loud shout from the multitude. See Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1824), 580.
[149] Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1822), 422-425.
[150] Duff, India and India Missions, 262-263.
[151] John Bentley, On the Effect of the Native Press in India, in Essays Relative to the Habits, Character, and Moral Improvement of the Hindoos (London: Kingsbury, Parbury, and Allen, 1823), 140-158. These essays were originally published in Calcutta s Friend of India, a newspaper associated with the Serampore Baptists.
[152] Ibid., 153-54
[153] Ibid., 142
[154] Ibid., 151-153
[155] Ibid., 156-158
[156] The Missionary Register, for instance, praised the newspaper the Samachar Darpan for the light it has diffused during its nineteen years in Calcutta and its inculcation of a a spirit of reading among the Hindoos. See Native Press and Literature at Calcutta, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1830), 356-357.
[157] The report claimed that people had begun to read, and reflect, and judge for themselves. See Decreasing Influence of the Brahmins, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1829), 450.
[158] Corruption of the Native Press, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1822), 336-337.
[159] Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1831), 358.
[160] Homi Bhabha, Signs Taken for Wonders: Questions of ambivalence and authority under a tree outside
Delhi, May 1817, in The Location of Culture (London and New York: Routledge, 1994), 102-122. Cf. Visit of Anund Messeeh to Delhi; and his Discovery of an extraordinary Body of Native Christians, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1818), 17-18.
[161] Eagerness of the Natives for Tracts, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1827), 384.
[162] Gyan Prakash, The Impossibility of Subaltern History, Nepantla: Views from the South 1.2 (2000): 288.
[163] Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1830), 541-42.
[164] For the yogi, see Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1819), 143. For the Bengali Ramayana, see Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1821), 157.
[165] Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1829), 316.
[166] Missionary Register ((London: L.B. Seeley, 1819), 277-281. This story seems to have previously been printed in Calcutta s Asiatic Researches.
[167] Illustration of Hindoo Craft and Credulity, Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley, 1821), 113-115.
[168] The Colossus of the Advertising World: The Press and the People, Oriental News, October 18, 1857
[169] Poona Observer, March 11, 1862
[170] Bombay Times and Journal of Commerce, January 3, 1859
[171] This, of course, is an early instance of the phenomenon analyzed by Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist
Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse? (London: Zed Books, 1986); and Dipesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000).
[172] Indian Journalism, Bombay Saturday Review, April 28, 1866
[173] Anglo-Indian Press, Poona Observer, June, 18 1861
[174] Poona Observer, June 20, 1861
[175] Constitutionalism in India, Telegraph and Courier (Bombay), April 8, 1861
[176] Poona Observer, June 20, 1861. Cf. C. A. Bayley, Empire and Information: Intelligence Gathering and Social Communication in India, 1780-1870 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
[177] The phrase insane rivalry of the old Bombay dailies derives from the Times of India, shortly after its amalgamation of the Bombay Times, the Bombay Standard, and the Telegraph and Courier. Quoted in Bombay Gazette (the TOI s chief rival) in November 11, 1861. For a chart that describes all of the papers in a slightly earlier period, see the Bombay Telegraph and Courier June 16, 1847.
[178] , June 27, 1861
[179] Bombay Gazette, June 20, 1861 (emphasis original)
[180] Poona Observer, January 30, 1862
[181] Poona Observer, August 29, 1861
[182] Oriental News, September 20, 1857
[183] For instance, on April 8, 1861, Bombay s Telegraph and Courier reported receipt of papers from Calcutta, Madras, and the Northwest Provinces, plus the Poona Observer.
[184] , October 31, 1861.
[185] Poona Observer, December 28, 1861
[186] Bombay Gazette, November 13, 1861
[187] Telegraph and Courier (Bombay), April 11, 1861
[188] , August 20, 1861.
[189] Public Opinion in Bombay, Bombay Saturday Review, February 1, 1862
[190] Bombay Saturday Review, October 12, 1861
[191] Bombay Gazette, January 25, 1861
[192] Bombay Gazette, May 17, 1862
[193] , February 25, 1862
[194] Poona Observer, August 1, 1861
[195] Poona Observer, October 26, 1861
[196] Poona Observer, May 9, 1861
[197] Duff, India and India Missions, 199.
[198] Statham, Indian Recollections, 69.
[199] See Randall Styers Making Magic: Religion, Magic, and Science in the Modern World (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004), 219-220.
[200] Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, vol. 2, Mythical Thought, trans. Ralph Mannheim (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1955). Cited in Styers, Making Magic, 220.
[201] J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words, 1955 William James Lectures (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975).
[202] Simon During, Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002).
[203] Missionary Register (London: L. B. Seeley, 1831), 357, emphasis original.
[204] Slavoj &i ek, The Spectre of Ideology, in Mapping Ideology, ed. Slavoj &i ek (London: Verso, 1994), 6.
[205] Book X, Chapter 33, Verse 21. The translation above is James Reddington s from his Vallabh"c"rya on the
Love Games of K&%!a (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1983), 255. Reddington s translation follows the gloss of ViTThala, Vallabha s son, who insists that the Sanskrit sva be understood as indicating the gopis very selves (ibid., 256). Compare Edwin Bryant s translation: you had abandoned relatives, the Vedas, and the world for my sake. See Krishna: The Beautiful Legend of God ( r(mad Bh"gavata Pur"!a Book X), trans. Edwin Bryant (New York: Penguin, 2003), 139.
[206] As quoted in Bombay Gazette, 4 December 1861, a propos of Karsandas Mulji. The quotation is from Bacon s essay Of Superstition.
[207] B. N. Motiwala, Karsondas Mulji: A Biographical Study (Bombay: Karsondas Mulji Centenary Celebration Committee, 1935), 33.
[208] Karsand!s M+lj$, Pop yurap kha*-n! m!h!r!jo, in Nibandhamala: Essays on Social Subjects by Karsandas Mulji (Bombay: Union Press, 1870), 152-156.
[209] David L. Haberman, "On Trial: The Love of the Sixteen Thousand Gopees," History of Religions 33:1 (1993):
[210] .
[211] Report of the Maharaj Libel Case and of the Bhattia Conspiracy Case, Connected With It. Jadunathjee Birzrattanjee Maharaj, vs. Karsandass Mooljee Editor and Proprietor, and Nanabhai Rastamji Ranina, Printer, Satya Prakash (Bombay: Bombay Gazette Press, 1862), 44-45. Henceforth cited in text as MLC.
[212] je tar+* pur+(o agy!n ane vahemn$ be-$o to-$ tath! m+rkh ane du() gur+on$ j!,m!#th$ cha)$ svadesh +nnati karv!m!# ma*-y! che. See Mah$patr!m R+pr!m, Uttam Kapo): Karsand"s Mu)j( Caritra (Amd!v!d: Amd!v!d Yun!i)e- Prin)$ng, 1877), i.
[213] The Bombay Samachar was founded in 1822, the Mumbai Vartaman in 1830, and the Jam-e Jamshed in 1832. Parsi dominance of the industry continued through the late 1850s. See Christine Dobbin, Urban Leadership in Western India: Politics and Communities in Bombay City 1840-1885 (London: Oxford University Press, 1972).
[214] Holi, Rast Goftar (Bombay), March 13, 1859; M!h!r!jn! mand$rm!# vesh$!no n!c, Rast Goftar, August 21, 1859; Va$snavon! m!h!r!jo b!be, Rast Goftar, May 22, 1859; V$shnav lokon$ hama*!n$ h!lat, Rast
Goftar, January 30, 1859
[215] V$.navon! m!h!r!jo $.var che ke !dm$ che?, R"st Goft"r, January 30, 1859; Va$snavon! m!h!r!jo, R"st Goft"r, June 19, 1859. See also M!h!r!j tath! v$.navone cetava*$, R"st Goft"r, January 23, 1859.
[216] Narmad, in particular, is a crucial figure in the history of modern Gujarati literature and has been dubbed the grand litterateur of the golden age of modern Gujarati ( govardhanyugn! garv! s!k(ar ). See Vijayarai Kalyanrai Vaidya, Gujarati Sahitya Ruparekha (Amd!v!d: Ravani Prakashan G/h, 1973), 282.
[217] Dobbin, Urban Leadership, 65-66
[218] Karsandas Mulji, H$nduno asal dharm ne h!ln! p!kha*-$ mato, Satya Prak"sh October, 21 1860. Reprinted in M"h"r"j L"(bal Kes tath" en( s"the sambandh rakhnar Bh"ti" Kansp(res( Kes (Mumbai: Daftar %.k!r! Ch!pkh!na, 1862), 1-3.
[219] Rast Goftar, October 21, 1860. I have not been able to locate a copy of the Satya Prakash from that date.
[220] The bite of hypocrisy [p!kha*-$] is dulled by the legalistic heterodoxy ; original [asal] is anthropologized by primitive ; dharma loses some of its semantic mobility when rendered as religion. Mulji, H$nduno asal dharm.
[221] lokone dekht$ !#khe !ndhl! karv!, ane teon$ !#khm! dhul ch!#)$ne dharmne n!me ane dharmne b!ne teon$ k!c$ kuv!r$ vahu d$kr$ bhogavv$ en!# kart! vadh!re p!kha*- ane vadh!re )hag!$ kah$? Mulji, Hinduno asal dharma.
[222] For an evocative description of Sausse the Silent, see High Court at Bombay, 1862-1962 (Bombay: Government Central Press, 1962).
[223] Poona Observer, January 30, 1862
[224] Poona Observer, February 13, 1862
[225] Poona Observer, February 22, 1862; Poona Observer, March 11, 1862
[226] Bombay Gazette, December 4, 1861
[227] Poona Observer, March 11, 1862. The couplet, incidentally, is the first illustration of the word priestcraft in the Oxford English Dictionary.
[228] Quoted in Poona Observer, February 22, 1862
[229] Bombay Gazette, May 1, 1862
[230] Times of India, May 2, 1862. Quoted in Karsandas Mulji, History of the Sect of Maharajas, or Vallabhacharyas in Western India (London: Tr bner & Co, 1865), 134. The book was published anonymously, but the scholarly consensus is that it was authored by Mulji.
[231] The Friend of India (Calcutta), quoted in Dnyanodaya (Bombay), June 2, 1862. With its missionary affiliations, the paper also quickly added that the light let into the hideous recesses of Wallabhacharya obscenity by the evidence in this case, far more than confirms all the statements of such scholars as Ward and H. H. Wilson.
[232] Dnyanodaya, June 2, 1862
[233] Bhattia Conspiracy Case, Bombay Saturday Review, December 21, 1861
[234] L!$beln! mukadam!no s!r, R"st Goft"r tath" Satya Prak"sh, February 23, 1862.
[235] R"st Goft"r tath" Satya Prak"sh, March 23, 1862
[236] R"st Goft"r tath" Satya Prak"sh, April 27, 1862
[237] L!$bal kesn$ asar kev$ +pav$ jo$e,? R"st Goft"r tath" Satya Prak"sh, 18 May 1862
[238] One might compare the Gujarati: te dharm sa#bandh$ nath$, pa* n$t$ sa#bandh$ che. M"h"r"j L"(bal
Kes.
[239] Gauri Viswanathan, Secularism in the Framework of Heterodoxy, PMLA 123.2 (2008): 466-476.
[240] Mulji, Hindun! Asal Dharma, ibid.
[241] See, for instance, kharo dharm tath! kharo m!rg and $.varbhakti ane n$ti, in Karsand!s M+,j$, N(tiVacan, ed. Ke.avpras!d Chot!l!l De.!$, 6th ed. (Amd!v!d: J$vanl!l Amar.$ Mahet!, 1923), 68-70 and 127138.
[242] Amrita Shodhan A Question of Community: Religious Groups and Colonial Law (Calcutta: Samya, 2001), 150.
[243] Ibid., 124-125. If the early 1860s were volatile years for Bombay culture, this was surely in part because of the period s economic volatility: the American Civil War pushed Bombay to the forefront of the global cotton market, prompting a massive financial bubble that, for a short time, drowned the city in champagne.
[244] Dobbin, Urban Leadership, 67; Karsandas Mulji, The Slavery Bond, Nibandhamala, 133-142.
[245] Shodhan, Question of Community, 138.
[246] See Naheed Fatima Ahmad, A History of Elphinstone College, 1827-1890: A Case Study in the Early Formation of an English-Educated Intelligentsia in Bombay (Ph.D. thesis, Oxford University, 1982).
[247] Elphinstone College Files, vol. 3 (1842), Correspondence addressed to the Secretary of the Elphinstone Native Institution for January 1842- December 1842, pp. 4-183; vol. 6 (1846-50), Correspondence relating to accounts for the years 1846, 1847, 1848 & 1850 for Subscription to the Elphinstone Institution and Books supplied by the Elphinstone Institution to Regimental and Government Schools ; vol. 8 (1848),
Correspondence addressed to the Secetrary of the Elphinstone Institution Bombay January-December 1848, relating to supply of books for distribution of prizes in the Government Vernacular Schools, Maharashtra State Archives, Mumbai.
[248] Quoted in Dobbin, Urban Leadership, 53.
[249] Leela Gandhi, Affective Communities: Anticolonial Thought, Fin-de-si cle Radicalism, and the Politics of Friendship (Durham: Duke University Press, 2006), 94.
[250] Bombay Gazette, April 23, 1862
[251] They have denounced They have exposed them. At a risk and to a cost which we cannot adequately measure, these men have done determined battle against a foul and powerful delusion. They have dared to look Custom and Error boldly in the face, and proclaim before the world of their votaries, that their Evil is not Good, that their Lie is not the Truth. In this doing, they have done bravely and well (MLC, 480).
[252] Erskine Perry, Cases Illustrative of Oriental Life and the Application of English Law to India, Decided in H. M.
Supreme Court at Bombay (London: S. Sweet, 1853), iv.
[253] Narmad!.a#kar L!l.a#kar, M"r( Hak(kat, ed. Ramesh M. Shukla (Amd!v!d: P!r.va Pablike.an, 2003), 102.
[254] Yadun!th Mah!r!j Suratv!,!, Svadharm vardhak ane sanshay chedek, vol. 1 (Amd!v!d: Gujarat Printing Press, 1911), i. Notably, Jadunath finesses his double role as publicist and protector of the true religion by refraining from quoting #ruti scriptures (anyone, even a shudra, can read a pamphlet); instead, he simply mentions that such a matter (v!t) is in the Ved somewhere, and the reader is to accept him on his word.
[255] G nther-Dietz Sontheimer and Hermann Kulke, Hinduism Reconsidered (New Delhi: Manohar
Publications, 1989); Vasudha Dalmia and Heinrich von Stietencron, Representing Hinduism: The Construction of Religious Traditions and National Identity (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 1995); Who Speaks for Hinduism? spec. issue of Journal of the American Academy of Religion 68.4 (2000). For a discussion of the broader discursive field into which the newly reconstituted object Hinduism entered, see Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions, or, How European Universalism was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005).
[256] J rgen L tt, From Krishnalila to Ramarajya: A Court Case and Its Consequences for the Reformulation of
Hinduism, in Representing Hinduism, ibid., 142-153. N. A. Thoothi has likewise suggested that Gujarati Vaishnavism has witnessed a general decline in emphasis on the Bhagavat Purana with concomitant rise in prominence for the Gita and Ram. See The Vaishnavas of Gujarat (Calcutta: Longmans, Green & Co., 1935), 74.
[257] Haberman, "On Trial
[258] A demurrer is a plea filed by the defense to challenge the legal sufficiency of the claim made by the complaining party.
[259] Horace Hayman Wilson, Sketch of the Religious Sects of the Hindus (Calcutta: Bishop s College Press, 1846),
[260] -78. Some of this material was republished shortly after the affair by the Bombay Gazette (September 17, 1862).
[261] Sir Monier Monier-Williams, Hinduism (Delhi: Rare Books, 1971), 142-48. Compare Sir Monier Monier-
Williams, Religious Thought and Life in India: An Account of the Religions of the Indian Peoples, Based on a Life s Study of their Literature and on Personal Investigations in their own Country, vol. 1 (London: John Murray, 1883), 148-155.
[262] Karsandas Mulji, N(ti-Vacan, ibid., 3. The printing of the N(ti-Vacan was announced in the R"st Goft"r on July, 3 1859 ( N$ti Vacan Pustak ). Essays collected in the volume were previously published in the Satya Prakash and the N(tibodhak between 1855 and 1858.
[263] sarva pr!*$onne j$vt! r!khe che ; Karsandas Mulji, God, in N(ti-Vacan, 1.
[264] Rupram, Uttam Kapo), ii.
[265] Yadun!th Mah!r!j, Svadharm Vardhak, vol. 2, 22-24
[266] Gandhi, Affective Communities, 126-27.
[267] Ibid., 129.
[268] Ibid, 131.
[269] Thoothi, Vaishnavas of Gujarat, 75-76.
[270] Arcana is generally understood to refer specifically to puja (i.e. the worship of icons). Jadunathji is at some pains, however, to distance his devotional prescriptions from m+rti puja. In this, he is fully consistent with Pu()im!rgi tradition. See Richard Barz, The Bhakti Sect of Vallabhacarya (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1992 [1976]), 46-52.
[271] Yadunath Maharaj Svadharm vardhak, vol. 2, 9-20
[272] See John Stratton Hawley, The Memory of Love: Surdas Sings to Krishna (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).
[273] For discussions of Vallabhacharya s life and teachings, see the following studies: Mrudula Marfatia, The Philosophy of Vallabhacarya (Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1967); Manilal C. Parekh, Shri Vallabhacharya: Life, Teachings, and Movement (A Religion of Grace) (Rajkot: Harmony House, 1969); Richard Barz, Bhakti Sect of Vallabhacarya, ibid.; Chimanlal Vaidya, Shri Vallabhacharya and His Teachings, trans. Bhailalbhai N. Shastri (Baroda: Shri Vallabha Publications, 1984); Maya Burger, The Hindu Model of Social Organization and the Bhakti Movement: The Example of Vallabha s Sampradaya, in Devotional Literature in South Asia: Current Research, 1985-1988, ed. R. S. McGregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 56-66; Peter Bennett, The Path of Grace: Social Organization and Temple Worship in a Vaishnava Sect (Delhi: Hindustan Publishing Company, 1993).
[274] Barz, 81-85. The !tm!-nivedan mantra of the samprad!ya is as follows: Om. The God Krishna is my refuge [Srikrsna saranam mama]. Distracted by the infinite pain and torment caused by the separation from Krishna, which has extended over a space of time measured by thousands of years, I now, to the holy Krishna, do dedicate [samarpay"m(] my bodily faculties, my life, my soul, and its belongings, with my wife, my house, my children, my whole substance, and my own self. O Krishna; I am thy servant [d"sa]. F. S. Growse, Mathura: A District Memoir (Allahabad: N. W. Provinces and Oudh Government Press), 287. Cited in Barz, 85.
[275] The theological resonance with the Protestant salvation by faith alone is discussed in J rgen L tt, Max Weber and the Vallabhacharis, International Sociology 2. 3 (September 1987): 277-287.
[276] Quoted in Barz, 33
[277] Quoted in Barz, 34
[278] Barz, 92
[279] Barz, 46-49
[280] For discussions of Vallabha s intervention into Advaita Vedanta, see Marfatia, The Philosophy of Vallabhacarya, and Barz, 56-79.
[281] Elsewhere, he refutes the claim that the entire world (jagat) is the child (chokara) of maya, insisting instead that it is one of being with god, or arose from within god s soul (! jagat bhagv!n n! !tm! m!heth$ +tpann thayu# che). Yadun!th Mah!r!j, Svadharam Vardhak, vol. 1, 7
[282] Christopher Pinney interprets the guru s dhoti dirt semiotically as an index of his holy presence; he suggests that the symbolic economy of bhakti devotion be read in parallel to that of the court, with its photographic standards of evidence. See Christopher Pinney, The Coming of Photography in India (London: British Library, 2008).
[283] Stree Bodh, January 1861. Many of the essays from Stree Bodh were later collected in the volume Karsand!s M+lj$, Sans"rsukh: Domestic Happiness (Mumbai: Rising Star Printing Press, 1887 [1860]), i. For additional contextualization and celebration of the Stree Bodh, see the essays in Sir George Birwood, ed, The Stree Bodh and Social Progress in India: A Jubilee Memorial (Bombay: The Stree Bodh Office, 1908).
[284] Barz, 89-90
[285] prabhun! svar+pm! mitrn$ pe)he sneh v!ch,t! r!khv$ ane mitrn$ pethe ten! dar.an karv!m!# !turt! r!khv$. Yadun!th Mah!r!j, Svadharm Vardhak, vol. 1, 18.
[286] Ibid., vol. 2, 21-24
[287] Mulji, H$nduon! asal dharm
[288] Behramji M. Malabari, Gujarat and the Gujaratis (Delhi: Mittal Publications, 1983 [1889]), 226-227.
[289] It is unspeakably sad to find men and women, whose lives in other respects are regulated by the best domestic and social virtues, men of keen wits and women of pure habits, becoming so utterly infatuated by a vile tradition a tissue of fantastic fables and transparent myths . What power of faith is theirs! But how perverted! (ibid., 129).
[290] Ibid, 129
[291] Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty (Oxford: Blackwell, 1969).
[292] Simon During, Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), 48-49.
[293] Gauri Viswanathan, Outside the Fold: Conversion, Modernity, Belief (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998), 88, 97.
[294] On influence, cf. David Gilmartin, Election Law and the People in Colonial and Postcolonial India, in From the Colonial to the Postcolonial: India and Pakistan in Transition, ed. Dipesh Chakrabarty, Rochona Majumdar, and Andrew Sartori (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2007), 55-84.
[295] Sean Latham, The Art of Scandal: Modernism, Libel Law, and the Roman Clef (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 78.
[296] Francis Ludlow Holt, The Law of Libel, in which is Contained a General History of this Law in the Ancient Codes and of its Introduction and Successive Alterations in the Law of England, Comprehending a Digest of All the Leading Cases upon Libels, from the Earliest to the Present Time (New York: Stephen Gould, 1818 [London, 1812]). See also William Blake Odgers, A Digest of the Law of Libel and Slander (London: Stevens and Sons, 1881); Peter Frederick Carter-Ruck, Libel and Slander (Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 1973); Sean Latham, The Art of Scandal, 69-88.
[297] Latham, 75-77; Indian Penal Code Section 299 lists three exceptions to the illegality of defamation: (1) imputation of truth which public good requires to be made or published, (2) public conduct of public servants, and (3) conduct of any person touching any public question.
[298] As one legal primer puts it, [e]ven if in a sense newspapers owe a duty to their readers to publish any and every item of news that may interest them, this is not such a duty as makes every communication in the paper relating to a matter of public interest a privileged one. Ratanlal Ranchhoddas and Dhirajlal Keshavlal Thakore, The English and Indian Law of Torts, 19th ed. (Bombay: Bombay Law Reporter Private Ltd, 1965 [1897]), 174.
[299] Cf. Michael Warner, The Letters of the Republic: Publication and the Public Sphere in Eighteenth-Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
[300] Ranchhoddas and Thakore, English and Indian Law of Torts, 181.
[301] Ranchhoddas and Thakore specify several modes of libel distinctive to the Indian context. For instance, if one sends a letter in the Urdu script to a person not conversant with that script, who then has a third party read the letter to him, this act of publication cannot qualify as libel if the sender of the letter did not know that the recipient did not read Urdu. In addition, it amounts to defamation to publicly exhibit an effigy of a person and then beat it with shoes; to write a letter to man that accuses his wife of witchcraft; or to claim that a man s wife is of low caste (English and Indian Law of Torts, 170-73).
[302] Ibid., 171.
[303] Indian Penal Code (1860), chapter XXI.
[304] Ibid., 164-65.
[305] Ibid., 182.
[306] Anstey claimed that, if the case were tried in England where the courts do entertain spiritual suits, the Court of Common Law would decline to entertain it, but would rather refer it to the Ecclesiastical or Courts Christian. The Court of Common Law can never assume a concurrent jurisdiction with the Ecclesiastical Court, and will refer to the latter all defamation cases pertaining to it (MLC, 14-15).
[307] Bombay Gazette, May 3, 1862
[308] Bombay Gazette, May 1, 1862
[309] Bombay Gazette, July 16, 1862
[310] The much-quoted Judge Arnould: It may be allowable to express a hope that what they [Mulji et al] have done will not have been in vain that the seed they have sown will bear its fruit that their courage and consistency will be rewarded by a steady increase in the number of those, whom their words and their examples have quickened into thought and animated to resistance, whose homes they have helped to cleanse from loathsome lewdness and whose souls they have set free from a debasing bondage (MLC, 480).
[311] Poona Observer, March 11, 1862
[312] See James C. Masselos, The Khojas of Bombay: The Defining if Formal Membership Criteria During the
Nineteenth Century, in Caste and Social Stratification among Muslims, ed. Imtiaz Ahmad (Delhi: Manohar, 1973), 1-20; Amrita Shodhan, A Question of Community, ibid; Teena Purohit, Formations and Genealogies of Ismaili Sectarianism in Nineteenth Century India (Ph.D. thesis, Columbia University, 2007).
[313] The Observer decries the new policy at the Friend of India of demanding the compulsory prepayment of postage. The paper duty is nothing to this compulsory prepayment; the Income Tax, injurious as it is, is
[314] SP, 303-305
[315] Dayanand included this story in the 1879 autobiography that he composed for The Theosophist. The valuation placed upon it here follows the way in which the adult Dayanand himself positioned this event as the major transformative moment of his childhood. Autobiography of Dayanand Saraswati, Swami The Theosophist 1.1 (October 1879): 9-13.
[316] For an argument as to why Dayanand should be considered a fundamentalist, see J. E. Llewellyn, The Arya Samaj as a Fundamentalist Movement (New Delhi: Mahohar, 1993).
[317] Mahar(i Day!nand Saraswat$, Saty"rth Prak"# (Dill$: %rya Pariv!r Yojn!, 2007). (Henceforth cited in text as SP).
[318] I borrow the phrase creative adaptation from Dilip Parameshwar Gaonkar, On Alternative Modernities, in Alternative Modernities, ed. Dilip Parameshwar Gaonkar (Durham: Duke University Press, 2001), 1-23.
[319] I would clarify that I do not think that either set of discourses is pre-given as a coherent tradition of critical thought; rather, they are marshaled as traditions, and as distinct ones at that, precisely by interventions such as Day!nand s.
[320] Although I have in my possession a heap of papers pertaining to the scandalous fourteenth chapter of the Saty"rth Prak"sh, which takes the Prophet and the Qur an to task, I have decided to defer analysis of that material. This chapter is preliminary to that project. Here, I work through the imaginary of imposture developed by Day!nand in the main body of the Saty"rth Prak"sh. Whether the fourteenth chapter was or was not, as sometimes alleged, a later interpolation into Day!nand s magnum opus, its general method is certainly not in keeping with the first twelve chapters of the text, and so it would serve as a strange point of entry onto Day!nand s reformist project. Having worked through the problematic of fraud in the pivotal eleventh chapter, I plan to return to Day!nand s critique of the Qur an and the controversy it occasioned in Sindh in the early 1940s at a later date.
[321] The only autobiographical reflections authored by Day!nand are the three essays that he published in The Theosophist in 1879-1880. He composed in Hindi, and his account was then translated into English; the Hindi original was not published, although an alleged copy surfaced in the late twentieth century.
Autobiography of Dayanand Saraswati, Swami The Theosophist 1.1 (October 1879): 9-13; Theosophist 1.3 (December 1879): 66-68; and Theosophist 2.2 (November 1880): 24-26. Major biographies in English written by Arya Samajis, often with hagiographical tendencies, include Bawa Chhaju Singh, Life and Teachings of Swami Dayanand Saraswati (New Delhi: Jan Gyan Prakashan, 1971 [1903]); Har Bilas Sarda, Life of Dayanand Saraswati, World Teacher (Ajmer: Vedic Yantralaya, 1946). The most thorough scholarly biography is J. T. H. Jordans, Day"nanda Sarasvat-: His Life and Ideas (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1978).
[322] Curiously, the original version of this narrative omits the mouse. The Autobiography published in The Theosophist only claims in a general sense that mice can run across m+rtis. The mouse assumes its canonical proportions in later literature, which elides the apparent absence at the heart of this primal scene. Jordans, for instance, includes the mouse (Day"nanda Saraswati, 5). Chhaju Singh likewise reports on the little creature ; he, however, re-enchants the moment by inserting the voice of an all-powerful Being who commands Day!nand to preach Vedic monotheism (Life and Teachings, 3-4).
[323] J. N. Farquhar, Modern Religious Movements in India (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1977 [1914]), 106-107.
[324] For Day!nand leaving Calcutta totally transformed, see Kenneth W. Jones, Arya Dharm: Hindu
Consciousness in 19th-Century Punjab (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976), 34-35.
[325] Ibid, 35.
[326] Farquhar, Modern Religious Movements, 109.
[327] Jones, Arya Dharm, 36-43.
[328] Farquhar, Modern Religious Movements, 101-128.
[329] Jones, Arya Dharm. The paradigm is further elaborated by Jones later survey of socio-religious reform movements, which divides movements into two major classes, acculterative (i.e. responding to British influence) and transitional (i.e. pursuing reform agendas unrelated to colonialism). See Socio-religious reform movements in British India (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
[330] Arguments for continuity include: Christophe Jaffrelot, The Hindu Nationalist Movement in India (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996 [1993]); A. R. Desai, Social Background of Indian Nationalism (Bombay: Popular Prakashan, 1976 [1948]); Daniel Gold, Organized Hinduisms: From Vedic Truth to Hindu Nation, in Martin Marty and J. Scott Abbleby, eds., Fundamentalisms Observed (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994): 531-93; Gene R. Thursby, Hindu-Muslim Relations in British India (Leidin: E. J. Brill, 1975).
Additionally, Jaffrelot begins his recent Hindu nationalism reader with a selection from the Saty"rth
[331] !ryy!vartt desh me# bh$ popj$ j!no l!kho# avat!r lekar l$l! phail! rahe hai# (SP, 232).
[332] Gauri Viswanathan, Secularism in the Framework of Heterodoxy, PMLA 123.2 (2008): 466-476.
[333] On Dayanand s interest in science, see Prakash, Another Reason.
[334] As discussed in Chapter 2, native convert Atamaran traveled to Puri to investigate the miracle of the Lord Jagganath s self-propelled chariot. When he saw that it was pulled by men, he accepted the truth of missionary Christianity. See Deceptions Practised on the Worshippers of Juggernaut, Missionary Register, December 1830, 541-542.
[335] See Leigh Eric Schmidt, Hearing Things: Religion, Illusion, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000); Simon During, Modern Enchantments: The Cultural Power of Secular Magic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002).
[336] Dayanand s tactical use of popery further mangles the cultural logic of caste and, in doing so, contributes to another major plank of his reform project. Dayanand deracinates his opponents by extruding them from their kinship networks into a space of popish exile. In this opening dialogue, Dayanand s fictive interlocutor resists being rechristened a pope by asserting that because he was born a brahman, he must still be a brahman. A person is always of the same caste as his mother and father. Dayanand corrects this claim sternly. Birth does not make a brahman. Virtue, deeds, and inner nature (gu*a, karma, and svabh!va) are what makes a brahman. Those who claim religious authority but lack virtue are to be called popes. This polemic epithet thus contributes to Dayanand s larger effort to reform caste by replacing the var*a of birth with the var*a of virtue. The assault on familial j!ti and var*a extends throughout the Saty"rth Prak"sh.
[337] As he wrote, his task is to critique (kha*-an-ma*-an karna) the religions of the Aryans (!ryya log), the people who live in India (jo ki !ryyavartt desh mem vasnev!le hai#) (SP, 227-229).
[338] Although it seems unlikely that Dayanand would have known any of these works there are no indications that he read English it is quite likely that historical arguments in this mould worked their way into polemics of the period. Orientalists, missionaries, Theosophists, Hindu reformists: all participated in the broad inquiry into the history of religions in one way or another.
[339] In the West, the typical categories were Judaism, Christianity, Muhammadanism, and Paganism. See Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions, or, How European Universalism was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005).
[340] Prakash, Another Reason, 119.
[341] Ibid., 90.
[342] jo sacc$ hai#, voh ved!di satyash!stro# k$ aur jo jh+)h$ hai#, vo in popo# ke pur!*r+p ghar k$ hai# (SP, 273).
[343] The Kabir panth is faulted for worshipping the bedstead, mattress, pillows, sandals, and lamp of the saint. Dayanand praises Guru Nanak s character, but faults him for his village language (gr!mo# k$ bh!(!) and ignorance of Sanskrit (SP, 296-299).
[344] The father lied about being married when he entered sanny!s; the son violated his sanny!s by marrying a low-caste girl (SP, 305).
[345] is$ prak!r mithy!j!l rac ke bic!re bhole manu(yo# ko j!l me# phas!y! aur apne !pko .r$k/(* m!nkar sabke sv!m$ m!nte hai# (SP, 305)
[346] The incantation tan-man-dhan also occurs elsewhere in the Saty"rth Prak"sh. See, for instance, the indictment of today s lineages of selfish brahmans (!jkal ke samprad!y$ aur sv!rth$ brahman) (65).
[347] Dayanand refers to these as bhagandar!di rog.
[348] v!h j$ v!h! acch! mat hai!! (SP, 305).
[349] Gyan Prakash, The Impossibility of Subaltern History, Nepantla: Views from the South 1:2 (2000): 288.
[350] Jordans, Dayananda, 7-18.
[351] In the autobiographical essay published in The Theosophist, Dayanand identified himself as having been born in Kathiawar, to a Brahmin family of the Oudichya [Audichya] caste.
[352] Jordans, Day"nanda, 7-13.
[353] jab aise h$ j!)j$ ke se pur+( ho#, to popl$l! sa#s!r me# na cale (SP, 284).
[354] t+ bh$ ais! h$ kar, nah$# to mer! aur ter! upah!s hog! (SP, 308).
[355] is$ prak!r vedvirodh$ sab samprad!yo# k$ l$l! hai (SP, 310).
[356] Missionary Register (London: L.B. Seeley,1819), 143.
[357] See Jordans, Day"nanda, 20.
[358] In addition to explicating the example of the serpent and the rope, Dayanand also gestures to other metaphors: the silver in a shell, the water in a mirage, a fairy city (gandharvanagar), and a sorcery (indraj!l). Dayanand also describes the serpent in the rope: andhak!r aur kuch prak!sh ke mel me# akasm!t rajj+ ko dekhne se sarp k! bhram hokar bhay se ka#pt! hai. jab usko d$p !di se dekh let! hai, us$ samay bhram aur bhay niv/tt ho j!t! hai. vaise brahm me# jo jagat k$ mithy! prat$ti hu$ hai, us k$ niv/tti aur brahm ki prat$ti) (SP, 239-40).
[359] For example, in one passage, the straw man Vedantin shirks duty (kartavya) by denying that there is a real difference between good and bad behavior (p!p-pu*ya). A person should simply recognize himself as brahm and rest content (santu() rahen!). Dayanand excoriates him: like ears that do not hear or eyes that do not see, these men are useless burdens on the world (SP, 111).
[360] jainmat k! kha*-an karne h$ ke liye (SP, 244).
[361] The phrase used to describe their reconversion to Vedism is vedmat k! sv$k!r kar liy! ; they accepted the Vedic religion (SP, 237-238).
[362] The important phrase here is that Shankara wandered India for ten years attacking the Jain religion and defending the Vedic religion; das var( ke bh$tar sarvatra !ry!vartt me# gh+mkar jainio# k! kha*-an aur vedo# k! ma*-an kiy! (SP, 237-238).
[363] Modern Vedantis (!j-kal ke ved!nti) babble falsely and uselessly (kutark$ vyarth bakna) and speak nonsense (are bakv!d karne w!le) (SP, 87).
[364] v!*$ h$ se sab vyavah!r siddh hote hai#; us v!*$ ko jo cort! arth!t mithy!bh!(a* kart! hai, voh sab cor$ !di p!po# k! karnev!l! hai (91).
[365] jais$ h!ni pratigy!-mithy! karne w!le k$ hot$ hai, vais$ anya kis$ k$ nah$# (35).
[366] vin! k!ra* apn$ m!y! se sab s/()i kha/$ kar d$ hai (SP, 275).
[367] parame.var me# chal-kapa)!di do( na hone se, usko m!y!v$ nah$# kahe sakte (SP, 275).
[368] m!y! manu(ya me# ho sakt$ hai, jo ki chal$-kapa)$ hai#, unh$# ko m!y!v$ kahete hai# (SP, 275).
[369] For a history of pilgrimages to the Braj region, see David Haberman, Journey Through the Twelve Forests: An encounter with Krishna (New York: Oxford, 1994).
[370] jah!# avidy! ne ghar kar rakkh! hai (SP, 305).
[371] L tt, From Krishnalila, 148.
[372] satya-mat k! ma*-an aur asatya k! kha*-an (SP, 226).
[373] satya-asatya mat sab ko vidit ho j!eg! (SP, 226).
[374] !ry!vartt$ya matpantho# k$ sam!locan! (SP, 5).
[375] mer! t!tparyya kiss$ k$ h!ni v! virodh karne me# nah$# (SP, 226).
[376] na ki v!dviv!d, virodh karne-kar!ne ke liye (SP, 226).
[377] In whatever matter the thousand sects are of one mind (jis b!t me# yeh sahestra ekmat ho#), that is to be taken as the Vedic religion (voh vedmat gr!hya hai). And in whatever matter there is dissension among them (jisme# paraspar virodh ho), that is be taken as imaginary, false, irreligious, and unacceptable (voh kalpit, jh+)h!, adharm, agr!hya hai) (318-319).
[378] Is religion in true speech or in illusion (satyabh!(a* me# dharm v! mithy! me#)?
[379] viruddh hote hai#, to ek ke vin! d+sr! dharm nah$# ho sakt! (316).
[380] Henry Steel Olcott, An Address by Col. Henry S. Olcott, President of the Theosophical Society, to the
Arya Samaj of Meerut, Delivered May 5th 1879, on the Occasion of a Public Welcome to a Committee of the Theosophical Society, by the Revered Swamee Daya Nand Saraswati, and the Meerut Samaj (Roorkee, India: Thomason Civil Engineering College Press, 1879), 2-4.
[381] A translation of the speech is to be found in Sarda, Life of Dayanand Saraswati. For additional description of the short-lived alliance between the Arya Samaj and the Theosophical Society, see Chhajju Singh, Life and Teachings, 476-532; Farquhar, Modern Religious Movements, 110, 226; Olcott, Old Diary Leaves, vol 1., 135, 394-40
[382] Quoted in A. R. Fausset, Spiritualism Tested by Scripture (London: Church of England Book Society, 1885), 13.
[383] H. P. Blavatsky to A. P. Sinnett, March 17, 1885 (ML-138), in The Mahatma Letters to A. P. Sinnett, eds. A. T. Barker and Vincente Hao Chin, Jr. (Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 1998), 443-448.
[384] Statement and Conclusions of the Committee, Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research 3 (1885): 207. Henceforth cited as SPR Proceedings.
[385] Richard Hodgson, Account of Personal Investigations in India and Discussion of the Authorship of the Koot Hoomi Lettes, Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research 3 (1885): 313-317.
[386] See Hent de Vries invocation of Levinas in In Media Res: Global Religion, Public Spheres, and the Task of Contemporary Comparative Religious Studies, in Religion and Media, ed. Hent de Vries and Samuel Weber (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001), 9.
[387] Henry Steel Olcott, Theosophy: Its Friends and Enemies, Address delivered at Framji Cowasji Institute, Bombay, 27 February 1881 (Bombay: Industrial Press, 1881), 16.
[388] Henry Steel Olcott diary, September 27, 1884, Nehru Memorial Library, New Delhi.
[389] Ibid., September 10, 1884.
[390] Preston Guardian, September 27, 1884.
[391] Graphic (London), September 27, 1884.
[392] Liverpool Mercury, October 13, 1884.
[393] Post (Bangalore), as quoted in Madras Times, September 17, 1884.
[394] Deccan Times (Madras), as quoted in Madras Times, September 22, 1884.
[395] SPR Proceedings, 203. The S.P.R. had been founded in 1882 to apply scientific methods to the study of psychical phenomena. From the first, it had many high-profile members, such as Cambridge professor of moral philosophy Henry Sidgwick; later associates would include figures as diverse as Lewis Carroll and Henri Bergson. The investigation of the Theosophical Society was one of the S.P.R. s earliest and most controversial undertakings. For a thorough account of the S.P.R. and its historical context, see Janet Oppenheim, The Other World: Spiritualism and Psychical Research In England, 1850-1914 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1985). For additional discussion of the S.P.R. s aims and the place of the Theosophical
[396] Henry Steel Olcott, Old Diary Leaves: The History of the Theosophical Society, vol. 3 (Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2002), 195-197.
[397] Ibid., 198-200
[398] The committee was chaired by Norendro Nath Sen, editor of the Indian Mirror and Honorary Magistrate,
Calcutta. Its members were as follows: A. J. Cooper-Oakley, Registrar, Madras University; Franz
Hartmann, M.D.; S. Ramaswamier, District Registrar, Madura; Naoroji Dorabji Khandalavala, Judge; H. R. Morgan, Major- General; Gyanendranath Chakrabarty, M.A., Inspector of Schools and formerly Professor of Mathematics, Allahabad; Nobin K. Bannerji, Deputy Collector and Magistrate; T. Subba Row, Pleader, High Court, Madras; P. Sreenivasrow, Judge; P. Iyaloo Naidu, Deputy Collector (Ret.); Rudolph Gebhard; R. Raghoonath Row, Deputy Collector, Madras and former Prime Minister, Indore; and S. Subramania Iyer, since knighted by H.M. Government and now Justice of the High Court, Madras. All information given in Olcott, Old Diary Leaves, vol. 3, 200-201.
[399] Ibid., 200-203
[400] Ibid., 202
[401] For the term counter-public, see Michael Warner, Publics and Counterpublics (New York: Zone Books, 2002).
[402] A. P. Sinnett, The Occult World, 9th ed. (London: Theosophical Publishing House, 1984 [1881]), 29.
[403] Stack to Sidgwick, 17 October 1884, Papers Relating to the Investigation of Madame Blavatsky, Archives of the Society for Psychical Research, Cambridge University Library (4/1/8/i/2-3).
[404] For summaries of contemporary newspaper coverage, see the Madras Times, September 17, 20, and 22, 1884.
[405] The Theosophist, October 1884, 1-2.
[406] Esoteric Buddhism II, Presbyterian Banner (Pittsburgh), April 28,1886. The official list for the Cambridge University Library special collection of materials pertaining to the S.P.R., where I found this newspaper clipping, dates it to April 28, 1884. This, of course, is more than a year before Hodgson published his report; a companion article is signed with the date April 7, 1886, and this article surely dates to the same year.
[407] South Australian Register, December 29, 1886; Boston Evening Transcript, May 8, 1887
[408] This claim is a tentative one. Indian-language papers tend not to have been preserved as meticulously as English papers; moreover, tracing the path of a scandal across vernacular India would require a range of linguistic competencies beyond the capacity of this, or surely any single, researcher.
[409] Here one might compare the coverage the Maharaj Libel Affair that the Dyanodaya, aspiring to lure Indians away from Hinduism, discussed in both languages.
[410] The Collapse of Koot Hoomi, Dnyanodaya, September 18, 1884. (I have retained the original transliteration of the bilingual journal s Marathi title, which served in English as well. It was accompanied by the translation Rise of Knowledge. )
[411] Satya Mitra tatha Hakha Mazdayasannam (Bombay), October 5 and 12, 1884.
[412] Karnal Henr$ Es %lk!4, Jarathoshti dharmni mul matlab vishe bh".a/ (Mumbai: Mumbai Sam!c!r, 1882).
[413] Satya Mitra, November 23, 1884.
[414] There may well have been something to these claims, as the Theosophists had for years opposed imperial rule. Consider, for instance, a letter to a Hindu that Olcott wrote from New York in 1878, in which he informed his correspondent that [w]hile we have no political designs, you will need no hint to understand that our sympathies are with all those who are deprived of the right of governing their own lands for themselves. I need say no more. Quoted in Hodgson, Account of Personal Investigations, 316.
[415] A. P. Sinnett, Incidents in the Life of Madame Blavatsky, Compiled from Information Supplied by her Relatives and Friends (London: Theosophical Publishing Society, 1913 [1886]), 228-229; Christian College Students and Theosophy, Madras Times, September 27, 1884; Arrival of Theosophists, Madras Mail, December 23, 1884; Madame Blavatsky and the Students of the Madras Colleges, The Theosophist, March 1885.
[416] J. D. B. Gribble, A Report of an Examination into the Blavatsky Correspondence, Published in the Christian College Magazine (Madras: Higginbotham and Co, 1884), 23-24.
[417] H. R. Morgan, Reply to a Report of an Examination into the Blavatsky Correspondence by J.D.B. Gribble, 2nd ed. (Ootacamud: Observer Press, 1884), i.
[418] Ibid., 6.
[419] Hodgon observes that [i]t is curious how much Babula has been kept in the background of Mr.
Sinnett s account; careless, no doubt, and not carefully. SPR Proceedings, 265-267
[420] Morgan, Reply to a Report, viii.
[421] See Partha Chatterjee, The Nation and Its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 6.
[422] Stack to Sidgwick, 17 October 1884, SPR.MSS.4/1/8/ii/4-5.
[423] The two psychical experiments are Dr. Elliotson s hypnosis research at the University College of London and Mr. Esdaile s at a Calcutta hospital. Elliotson, despite extensive training in hypnosis, found his human material was too intractable for his experiment to succeed. Esdaile, on the other hand, set to work at mesmerism almost by accident, and without any special knowledge whatever. But he found the Hindu subjects so susceptible that a conspicuous triumph was, so to speak, forced on him unawares. The unknown blind Bengalee succumbs, while the too wide-awake British eye resists the enchantments of magical authority. Hodgson writes that the S.P.R. have always desired and still desire to establish a psychical laboratory at Calcutta or Madras. See Richard Hodgson, First Report of the Committee of the Society for Psychical Research, Appointed to Investigate the Evidence for Marvellous Phenomena Offered by Certain Members of the Theosophical Society (London: National Press Agency, 1884), 10.
[424] Richard Hodgson, Madame Blavatsky and the Theosophical Society, proof for Contemporary Review (not published), 20 June 1885; see SPR.MSS.4/3/8/19.
[425] An Indian Scandal, The Graphic, May 2, 1885.
[426] See Homi K. Bhabha, The Other Question: Stereotype, Discrimination, and the Discourse of Colonialism, in The Location of Culture, (London and New York: Routledge, 1994), 66.
[427] In making a distinction between older Hindu elites who did little to modify their beliefs upon joining the Theosophical Society and the young recruits who cleaved more ardently to Blavatsky, I follow Moulton, The Beginnings of the Theosophical Movement in India, ibid., 109.
[428] Hodgson was exasperated by Chatterjee s testimonies, which often flatly contradicted those of other
Theosophists. Once, when recanting his earlier account of a Mahatma miracle, Chatterjee faulted his
[429] Chatterjee likewise deemphasizes the importance of the phenomena in S.P.R. Proceedings, 239
[430] For the term offmodern, see Sumathi Ramaswamy, The Lost Land of Lemuria: Fabulous Geographies, Catastrophic Histories (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California, 2004), 16-18.
[431] John William Draper, History of the Conflict between Religion and Science, 8th ed. (New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1878 [1874]), 367.
[432] Henry Steel Olcott, An Address by Col. Henry S. Olcott, President of the Theosophical Society, to the
Arya Samaj of Meerut, Delivered May 5th 1879, on the Occasion of a Public Welcome to a Committee of the Theosophical Society, by the Revered Swamee Daya Nand Saraswati, and the Meerut Samaj (Roorkee, India: Thomason Civil Engineering College Press, 1879), 8-9.
[433] Hodgson, First Report, 7. (emphasis in original)
[434] Warner, Publics and Counterpublics, 14.
[435] The Collapse of Koot Hoomi An Incident in the Early History of Theosophy in India. (London, Madras, and Colombo: Christian Literature Society, 1904), 2. This volume reprinted the entire series of articles originally published in the Madras Christian College Magazine in the autumn of 1884. The journal had been established in 1883 by Patterson and others as the Madras Missionary Magazine, and its express goal was to awaken or keep awake an interest in higher things, and in every social, moral, and literary question affecting India s present and future. It went on to become one of the best-known English-language journals intended primarily for a non-Christian readership. See G. A. Oddie, Social Protest in India: British
Protestant Missionaries and Social Reforms, 1850-1900 (Columbia, MO: South Asia Books, 1978), 43
[436] Collapse of Koot Hoomi, 1-2.
[437] See Leigh Eric Schmidt, Hearing Things: Religion, Illusion, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2000), especially Chapter 3, Oracles of Reason, 78-134.
[438] Still more comically, Emma reported having donned her Mahatma garb in the bathroom and wafted out onto the terrace. She poised herself below the window of the sitting room, where a party was assembled, and rose up dramatically, a prosthetic head amplifying her height. The reverent Theosophists saluted her, and she flitted back inside, stubbing her bare toe in the process. SPR Proceedings, 241-43.
[439] Fausset, Spiritualism Tested, 12.
[440] Arthur Lillie, Koot Hoomi Unveiled; or Tibeten Buddhists versus the Buddhists of Tibet (London: Psychological Press Association, c.1884).
[441] Josephine Ransom, A Short History of the Theosophical Society (Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 1938), 118.
[442] Henry Steel Olcott, Inaugural Address of the President-Founder of the Theosophical Society, Delivered at Mott Memorial Hall, New York City, at the First Regular Meeting of the Society, Nov. 17, 1875. Adyar Pamphlet Series, No. 5 (Benares and London: Theosophical Publishing Society, n.d.), 10.
[443] Ibid., 4-5
[444] Olcott diary, April 22, 1880.
[445] Morgan, Reply to a Report, xv.
[446] K. J. B. Wadia, Fifty Years of Theosophy in Bombay (Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 1931), 86. Blavatsky made use of the rhetoric of conspiracy in her own correspondence, as in a letter of March 1885, wherein she claimed that the 30,000 padris in India are all leagued against us. See H. P. Blavatsky to A. P. Sinnett, March 17, 1885 (ML-138), Mahatma Letters, 447. According to Koot Hoomi, the conspiracy extended all the way to the Vatican and to the Tibetan plateau, where the Dugpas were aligned with the Madras missionaries. This Great Game of occult subterfuge was, it seems, pan-Eurasian in scope. See Koot Hoomi to A. P. Sinnett, October 1884 (ML-55), Mahatma Letters, 431 80 The Theosophist, October 1884, 48-49.
[447] In fact, no amount of evidence is sufficient to confute them; they are more infallible than the Pope of Rome, and their evidence alone is to be received, and all else relegated to the limbo of the false (Morgan, Reply to a Report, 7).
[448] Ibid., 20-21.
[449] Ibid., 9.
[450] Olcott diary, January 15, 1885.
[451] H. P. Blavatsky, Isis Unveiled, ed. Boris de Zirkoff. 2 vols. (Adyar: Theosophical Publishing House, 2006 [1877]), vol. 1, page v. (Hereafter cited in text as IU).
[452] Here one might compare Michael Taussig: Blavatsky, in a sense, seeks to penetrate the veil while retaining its hallucinatory quality and to see the myth in the natural and the real in magic, to demythologize history and to reenact its reified representation. See Shamanism, Colonialism, and the Wild Man: A Study in Terror and Healing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 286, 473.
[453] Notably, the title was not quite Blavatsky s. Her publisher suggested an adjustment to her original title,
The Veil of Isis, when he discovered that it was already in use. See de Zirkoff, How Isis Unveiled was Written, 43. One might suggest that the ready interchangeability of the two titles underscores the doubleness of the Blavatskyian veil: whether the veil is on or off, it implies more or less the same thing.
[454] For further discussion of how Theosophy both bolstered and undermined British imperial ideologies, see Richard King, Orientalism and Religion: Postcolonial Theory, India and the Mystic East (New York and London: Routledge, 1999), especially Chapter 6, Mystic Hinduism ; and Viswanathan, Conversion, Theosophy, and Race Theory.
[455] Consider, for example, the account of Blavatsky s aunt Madame Nadjeda Fad eff : "je re us une lettre de celui que vous appelez, je crois, Kouth-humi, --qui me fut apport e de la mani re la plus incomprehensible et myst rieuse, dans ma maison, par un messager figure asiatique, qui disparut sous mes yeux m mes (First Report of the S.P.R., 113). The letter handed to Madame Fad eff was later taken to be the first Mahatma letter, predecessor to those sent to Sinnett. See C. Jinarajadas, The Story of the Mahatma Letters, 2nd ed. (Adyar:
Theosophical Publishing House, 2000 [1946]). For additional discussion of the ambivalences of the
Mahatma letters, see Viswanathan, The Ordinary Business of Occultism
[456] Edmund Garrett, Isis Very Much Unveiled: The Story of the Great Mahatma Hoax, 3rd ed. (London: Westminster Gazette Office, 1894).
[457] H. P. Blavatsky to A. P. Sinnett, March 18, 1885 (ML-138), Mahatma Letters, 447. The titles mentioned are Theosophy Unveiled, Madame Blavatsky Exposed, The Theosophical Humbug Before the World, and Christ against Mahatmas.
[458] Max Weber, Science as Vocation, in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), 139. See Viswanathan, Ordinary Business, for a discussion of the term disenthralment, which appears in the Mahatma letters to A. P. Sinnett and would seem to prefigure Weber s term disenchantment (Entzauberung).
[459] Hargrave Jennings, Review of The Occult World by A. P. Sinnett (Bombay: Gazette Steam Press, 1882), 13. (Hereafter cited in text as OWR).
[460] Morgan, Reply to a Report, x.
[461] Stack to Sidgwick, SPR.MSS.4/1/8/ii/1.
[462] Ibid., SPR.MSS.4/1/8/ii/9.
[463] Ibid., SPR.MSS.4/1/8/ii/13.
[464] Indeed, one might take this as the point of Viswanathan s analysis of Theosophy s bureaucratic obsessions in The Ordinary Business of Occultism.
[465] I borrow the phrase critical melancholia from Ranjana Khanna, Dark Continents: Psychoanalysis and Colonialism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2003).
[466] Here I paraphrase Kumkum Sangari, The Politics of the Possible, in The Nature and Context of Minority Discourse II, special issue, Cultural Critique 7 (Autumn 1987), 163.
[467] Damodar Mavalankar, Damodar: The Writings of a Hindu Chela, ed. Sven Eek (Point Loma, CA:
Theosophical University Press, 1940), 164. (emphasis in original)
[468] Koot Hoomi Lal Singh to A. P. Sinnett, October 17, 1880 (ML-1), Mahatma Letters, 5.
[469] The Religion of the Future, from Unpublished Writings of Eliphas Levi, quoted in The Theosophist, January 1885, 77.
[470] Ashis Nandy, The Intimate Enemy: Loss and Recovery of Self Under Colonaliasm (Delhi: Oxford, 1983).
[471] Report of the Thirty-Fifth Session of the Indian National Congress (1920), as cited in Amalendu Prasad Mookerjee, Social and Political Ideas of Bipin Chandra Pal (Calcutta: Minerva Associates Publications, 1974), 110.
[472] The Statesman, March 19, 1921, as cited in Mookerjee, ibid., 112-113.
[473] David Gilmartin, Election Law and the People in Colonial and Postcolonial India, in From the Colonial to the Postcolonial: India and Pakistan in Transition (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2007), 55-84.
[474] Srinivas Aravamudan, Guru English: South Asian Religion in a Cosmopolitan Language (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006).
[475] See Anthony Storr, Feet of Clay: Saints, Sinners, and Madmen: A Study of Gurus (New York: Free Press, 1996). 8 Osho, Priests and Politicians: The Mafia of the Soul (Delhi: Full Circle, 1999 [1987]), 77-79. The essay is entitled Zarathustra.
[476] Osho, Priests and Politicians, 23
[477] Jeremey R. Carrette and Richard King, Selling Spirituality: The Silent Takeover of Religion (New York: Routledge, 2005).
[478] Aamir Mufti, Critical Secularism: A Reintroduction for Perilous Times, boundary 2 31:2 (2004): 1-9.
[479] William D. Hart, Edward Said and the Religious Effects of Culture (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), ix.
[480] Edward W. Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983), 290.
[481] Edward W. Said, Orientalism (New York: Vintage Books, 1978).
[482] Jacques Derrida, Faith and Knowledge, trans. Sam Weber, in Acts of Religion, ed. Gil Anijdar, (New York: Routledge, 2002), 80-82.
[483] Slavoj &i ek, How the Non-Duped Err, Qui Parle 4.1 (1990): 9.
[484] Terry Eagleton, Reason, Faith, and Revolution: Reflections on the God Debate (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2009), 37.
[485] See Talal Asad, Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003), 16; Peter van der Veer, Imperial Encounters: Religion and Modernity in India and Britain (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 14.
[486] Representative titles include the following: Christopher Hitchens, God is not Great The Case Against
Religion (London: Atlantic Books, 2007); Richard Dawkins, The God Delusion (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2006); and Daniel Dennett, Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (New York: Viking, 2006). For a vivacious response, see Eagleton, Reason.
[487] See, for instance, in the introduction to this dissertation my discussion of Amartya Sen, The
Argumentative Indian: Writings on Indian History, Culture, and Identity (New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2005).
[488] Sumathi Ramaswamy, The Lost Land of Lemuria: Fabulous Geographies, Catastrophic Histories (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2004), 16. Ramaswamy, in elaborating the notion of the off-modern, is herself paraphrasing both Dipesh Chakrabarty and Svetlana Boym. In Boym s formulation, the offmodern veers from the straight road of progress to explore the back alleys of modernity. See Svetlana Boym, The Future of Nostalgia (New York: Basic Books, 2001).
[489] Mufti, Critical Secularism, 2-3
[490] Ibid., 3
[491] Gauri Viswanathan, Secularism in the Framework of Heterodoxy, PMLA 123.2 (2008): 466-476.
[492] Marcel Gauchet, The Disenchantment of the World: A Political History of Religion, trans. Oscar Burge (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997), 22. Gauchet attributes the rise of religion to humans inability to accept things for what they are. If Feuerbach and Marx tried to right illusion, helping the deluded to collapse the gods back into the themselves, Gauchet revisits the Hegelian dialectic to locate in religion the animating principle of history itself: religion represents the productive powers of negativity, splitting self-identical objects from within through the powers of the spirit.